You've studied the human mind, cognition, language, vision, evolution, psychology, from child to adult, from the level of individual to the level of our entire civilization, so I feel like I can start with a simple multiple choice question. What is the meaning of life? Is it A) to attain knowledge, as Plato said?
B) to attain power, as Nietzsche said? C) to escape death, as Ernest Becker said? D) to propagate our genes, as Darwin and others have said? E) there is no meaning, as the nihilists have said? F) knowing the meaning of life is beyond our cognitive capabilities, as Stephen Pinker said, based on my interpretation 20 years ago?
And G) none of the above? I'd say A comes closest, but I would amend that to attaining not only knowledge, but fulfillment more generally. That is, life, health, stimulation, access to the living cultural and social world. Now this is our meaning of life, it's not the meaning of life, if you were to ask our genes.
Their meaning is to propagate copies of themselves, but that is distinct from the meaning that the brain that they lead to sets for itself. So to you, knowledge is a small subset or a large subset? It's a large subset, but it's not the entirety of human striving, because we also want to interact with people, we want to experience beauty, we want to experience the richness of the natural world.
But understanding what makes the universe tick is way up there. For some of us more than others, certainly for me that's one of the top five. So is that a fundamental aspect? Are you just describing your own preference, or is this a fundamental aspect of human nature, is to seek knowledge?
In your latest book, you talk about the power, the usefulness of rationality and reason and so on. Is that a fundamental nature of human beings, or is it something we should just strive for? It's both. We're capable of striving for it, because it is one of the things that make us what we are — Homo sapiens, wise men.
We are unusual among animals in the degree to which we acquire knowledge and use it to survive. We make tools, we strike agreements via language, we extract poisons, we predict the behavior of animals, we try to get at the workings of plants. And when I say "we," I don't just mean "we" in the modern West, but "we" as a species everywhere, which is how we've managed to occupy every niche on the planet, how we've managed to drive other animals to extinction.
And the refinement of reason in pursuit of human well-being, of health, happiness, social richness, cultural richness, is our main challenge in the present. That is, using our intellect, using our knowledge to figure out how the world works, how we work, in order to make discoveries and strike agreements that make us all better off in the long run.
Right. And you do that almost undeniably and in a data-driven way in your recent book. But I'd like to focus on the artificial intelligence aspect of things, and not just artificial intelligence, but natural intelligence too. So, 20 years ago, in the book you've written on how the mind works, you conjecture, again, am I right to interpret things?
You can correct me if I'm wrong, but you conjecture that human thought in the brain may be a result of a massive network of highly interconnected neurons. So, from this interconnectivity emerges thought. Compared to artificial neural networks, which we use for machine learning today, is there something fundamentally more complex, mysterious, even magical about the biological neural networks versus the ones we've been starting to use over the past 60 years and have become to success in the past 10?
There is something a little bit mysterious about the human neural networks, which is that each one of us who is a neural network knows that we ourselves are conscious. Conscious not in the sense of registering our surroundings or even registering our internal state, but in having subjective first-person present-tense experience.
That is, when I see red, it's not just different from green, but there's a redness to it that I feel. Whether an artificial system would experience that or not, I don't know, and I don't think I can know. That's why it's mysterious. If we had a perfectly lifelike robot that was behaviorally indistinguishable from a human, would we attribute consciousness to it, or ought we to attribute consciousness to it?
That's something that it's very hard to know. But putting that aside, putting aside that largely philosophical question, the question is, is there some difference between the human neural network and the ones that we're building in artificial intelligence will mean that we're, on the current trajectory, not going to reach the point where we've got a lifelike robot indistinguishable from a human, because the way their so-called neural networks are organized are different from the way ours are organized?
I think there's overlap, but I think there are some big differences that the current neural networks, current so-called deep learning systems are in reality not all that deep. That is, they are very good at extracting high-order statistical regularities, but most of the systems don't have a semantic level, a level of actual understanding of who did what to whom, why, where, how things work, what causes what else.
- Do you think that kind of thing can emerge as it does? So artificial neural networks are much smaller, the number of connections and so on, than the current human biological networks, but do you think, sort of, to go to consciousness or to go to this higher level semantic reasoning about things, do you think that can emerge with just a larger network, with a more richly, weirdly interconnected network?
- Separate, again, consciousness, because consciousness isn't even a matter of complexity. - It's a really weird one. - Yeah, you could sensibly ask the question of whether shrimp are conscious, for example. They're not terribly complex, but maybe they feel pain. So let's just put that part of it aside.
But I think sheer size of a neural network is not enough to give it structure and knowledge, but if it's suitably engineered, then why not? That is, we're neural networks, natural selection did a kind of equivalent of engineering of our brains, so I don't think there's anything mysterious in the sense that no system made out of silicon could ever do what a human brain can do.
I think it's possible in principle. Whether it'll ever happen depends not only on how clever we are in engineering these systems, but whether we even want to, whether that's even a sensible goal. That is, you can ask the question, is there any locomotion system that is as good as a human?
Well, we kind of want to do better than a human, ultimately, in terms of legged locomotion. There's no reason that humans should be our benchmark. They're tools that might be better in some ways. It may be that we can't duplicate a natural system because at some point it's so much cheaper to use a natural system that we're not going to invest more brainpower and resources.
So for example, we don't really have an exact substitute for wood. We still build houses out of wood, we still build furniture out of wood. We like the look, we like the feel. Wood has certain properties that synthetics don't. It's not that there's anything magical or mysterious about wood.
It's just that the extra steps of duplicating everything about wood is something we just haven't bothered because we have wood. Like when I say cotton, I mean, I'm wearing cotton clothing now. It feels much better than polyester. It's not that cotton has something magic in it. And it's not that we couldn't ever synthesize something exactly like cotton.
But at some point it's just not worth it. We've got cotton. And likewise, in the case of human intelligence, the goal of making an artificial system that is exactly like the human brain is a goal that we probably no one is going to pursue to the bitter end, I suspect.
Because if you want tools that do things better than humans, you're not going to care whether it does something like humans. So for example, diagnosing cancer or predicting the weather, why set humans as your benchmark? - But in general, I suspect you also believe that even if the human should not be a benchmark and we don't want to imitate humans in their system, there's a lot to be learned about how to create an artificial intelligence system by studying the human.
- Yeah, I think that's right. In the same way that to build flying machines, we want to understand the laws of aerodynamics, including birds, but not mimic the birds. - Right, exactly. - But they're the same laws. - You have a view on AI, artificial intelligence and safety, that from my perspective is refreshingly rational, or perhaps more importantly, has elements of positivity to it, which I think can be inspiring and empowering as opposed to paralyzing.
For many people, including AI researchers, the eventual existential threat of AI is obvious, not only possible, but obvious. And for many others, including AI researchers, the threat is not obvious. So Elon Musk is famously in the highly concerned about AI camp, saying things like AI is far more dangerous than nuclear weapons, and that AI will likely destroy human civilization.
So in February, he said that if Elon was really serious about AI, the threat of AI, he would stop building self-driving cars that he's doing very successfully as part of Tesla. Then he said, wow, if even Pinker doesn't understand the difference between narrow AI, like a car, and general AI, when the latter literally has a million times more compute power and an open-ended utility function, humanity is in deep trouble.
So first, what did you mean by the statement about Elon Musk should stop building self-driving cars if he's deeply concerned? - Not the last time that Elon Musk has fired off an intemperate tweet. - Yeah, well, we live in a world where Twitter has power. - Yes. Yeah, I think that there are two kinds of existential threat that have been discussed in connection with artificial intelligence, and I think that they're both incoherent.
One of them is a vague fear of AI takeover, that just as we subjugated animals and less technologically advanced peoples, so if we build something that's more advanced than us, it will inevitably turn us into pets or slaves or domesticated animal equivalents. I think this confuses intelligence with a will to power, that it so happens that in the intelligence system we are most familiar with, namely Homo sapiens, we are products of natural selection, which is a competitive process, and so bundled together with our problem-solving capacity are a number of nasty traits like dominance and exploitation and maximization of power and glory and resources and influence.
There's no reason to think that sheer problem-solving capability will set that as one of its goals. Its goals will be whatever we set its goals as, and as long as someone isn't building a megalomaniacal artificial intelligence, then there's no reason to think that it would naturally evolve in that direction.
Now, you might say, "Well, what if we gave it the goal of maximizing its own power source?" Well, that's a pretty stupid goal to give an autonomous system. You don't give it that goal. I mean, that's just self-evidently idiotic. - So if you look at the history of the world, there's been a lot of opportunities where engineers could instill in a system destructive power, and they choose not to because that's the natural process of engineering.
- Well, except for weapons. I mean, if you're building a weapon, its goal is to destroy people, and so I think there are good reasons to not build certain kinds of weapons. I think building nuclear weapons was a massive mistake. - You do. You think... So maybe pause on that because that is one of the serious threats.
Do you think that it was a mistake in a sense that it should have been stopped early on, or do you think it's just an unfortunate event of invention that this was invented? Do you think it's possible to stop, I guess, is the question I'm asking. - Yeah, it's hard to rewind the clock because, of course, it was invented in the context of World War II and the fear that the Nazis might develop one first.
Then once it was initiated for that reason, it was hard to turn off, especially since winning the war against the Japanese and the Nazis was such an overwhelming goal of every responsible person that there was just nothing that people wouldn't have done then to ensure victory. It's quite possible if World War II hadn't happened that nuclear weapons wouldn't have been invented.
We can't know, but I don't think it was by any means a necessity any more than some of the other weapon systems that were envisioned but never implemented, like planes that would disperse poison gas over cities like crop dusters, or systems to try to create earthquakes and tsunamis in enemy countries, to weaponize the weather, weaponize solar flares, all kinds of crazy schemes that we thought the better of.
I think analogies between nuclear weapons and artificial intelligence are fundamentally misguided because the whole point of nuclear weapons is to destroy things. The point of artificial intelligence is not to destroy things. The analogy is misleading. >>Corey: There's two artificial intelligence you mentioned. The first one that gets highly intelligent or power hungry.
>>Kaiser: Yeah, in a system that we design ourselves, where we give it the goals. Goals are external to the means to attain the goals. If we don't design an artificially intelligent system to maximize dominance, then it won't maximize dominance. It's just that we're so familiar with Homo sapiens, where these two traits come bundled together, particularly in men, that we are apt to confuse high intelligence with a will to power, but that's just an error.
The other fear is that will be collateral damage, that will give artificial intelligence a goal, like make paperclips, and it will pursue that goal so brilliantly that before we can stop it, it turns us into paperclips. We'll give it the goal of curing cancer, and it will turn us into guinea pigs for lethal experiments, or give it the goal of world peace, and its conception of world peace is no people, therefore no fighting, and so it will kill us all.
Now, I think these are utterly fanciful. In fact, I think they're actually self-defeating. They, first of all, assume that we're going to be so brilliant that we can design an artificial intelligence that can cure cancer, but so stupid that we don't specify what we mean by curing cancer in enough detail that it won't kill us in the process, and it assumes that the system will be so smart that it can cure cancer, but so idiotic that it can't figure out that what we mean by curing cancer is not killing everyone.
So I think that the collateral damage scenario, the value alignment problem, is also based on a misconception. - So one of the challenges, of course, we don't know how to build either system currently, or are we even close to knowing? Of course, those things can change overnight, but at this time, theorizing about it is very challenging in either direction, so that's probably at the core of the problem, is without that ability to reason about the real engineering things here at hand, is your imagination runs away with things.
- Exactly. - But let me sort of ask, what do you think was the motivation and the thought process of Elon Musk? I build autonomous vehicles, I study autonomous vehicles, I study Tesla autopilot, I think it is one of the greatest currently large-scale applications of artificial intelligence in the world.
It has potentially a very positive impact on society. So how does a person who's creating this very good, quote-unquote, narrow AI system also seem to be so concerned about this other general AI? What do you think is the motivation there? What do you think is the thinking process? - Well, you probably have to ask him, and he is notoriously flamboyant, impulsive, as we have just seen, to the detriment of his own goals of the health of a company.
So I don't know what's going on in his mind, you probably have to ask him. But I don't think the distinction between special-purpose AI and so-called general AI is relevant, that in the same way that special-purpose AI is not going to do anything conceivable in order to attain a goal.
All engineering systems are designed to trade off across multiple goals. When we built cars in the first place, we didn't forget to install brakes, because the goal of a car is to go fast. It occurred to people, yes, you want it to go fast, but not always, so you build in brakes too.
Likewise, if a car is going to be autonomous, and program it to take the shortest route to the airport, it's not going to take the diagonal and mow down people and trees and fences, because that's the shortest route. That's not what we mean by the shortest route when we program it, and that's just what an intelligence system is by definition.
It takes into account multiple constraints. The same is true, in fact, even more true of so-called general intelligence. That is, if it's genuinely intelligent, it's not going to pursue some goal single-mindedly, omitting every other consideration and collateral effect. That's not artificial and general intelligence, that's artificial stupidity. I agree with you, by the way, on the promise of autonomous vehicles for improving human welfare.
I think it's spectacular, and I'm surprised at how little press coverage notes that in the United States alone, something like 40,000 people die every year on the highways, vastly more than are killed by terrorists. We spend a trillion dollars on a war to combat deaths by terrorism, about half a dozen a year, whereas year in, year out, 40,000 people are massacred on the highways, which could be brought down to very close to zero.
I'm with you on the humanitarian benefit. Let me just mention that it's, as a person who's building these cars, it is a little bit offensive to me to say that engineers would be clueless enough not to engineer safety into systems. I often stay up at night thinking about those 40,000 people that are dying, and everything I try to engineer is to save those people's lives.
So every new invention that I'm super excited about, every new, and in all the deep learning literature and CVPR conferences and NIPS, everything I'm super excited about is all grounded in making it safe and help people. So I just don't see how that trajectory can all of a sudden slip into a situation where intelligence will be highly negative.
- You and I certainly agree on that, and I think that's only the beginning of the potential humanitarian benefits of artificial intelligence. There's been enormous attention to what are we gonna do with the people whose jobs are made obsolete by artificial intelligence, but very little attention given to the fact that the jobs that are gonna be made obsolete are horrible jobs.
The fact that people aren't gonna be picking crops and making beds and driving trucks and mining coal, these are soul-deadening jobs, and we have a whole literature sympathizing with the people stuck in these menial, mind-deadening, dangerous jobs. If we can eliminate them, this is a fantastic boon to humanity.
Now granted, you solve one problem and there's another one, namely how do we get these people a decent income, but if we're smart enough to invent machines that can make beds and put away dishes and handle hospital patients, I think we're smart enough to figure out how to redistribute income to apportion some of the vast economic savings to the human beings who will no longer be needed to make beds.
- Okay, Sam Harris says that it's obvious that eventually AI will be an existential risk. He's one of the people who says it's obvious. We don't know when the claim goes, but eventually it's obvious, and because we don't know when, we should worry about it now. It's a very interesting argument in my eyes.
So how do we think about timescale? How do we think about existential threats when we don't really, we know so little about the threat, unlike nuclear weapons perhaps, about this particular threat, that it could happen tomorrow, right? But very likely it won't. - Yeah, definitely. - Very likely it'd be 100 years away.
So how do we ignore it? How do we talk about it? Do we worry about it? How do we think about those? - What is it? - A threat that we can imagine. It's within the limits of our imagination, but not within our limits of understanding to accurately predict it.
- But what is the it that we're afraid of? - Oh, AI, sorry, AI being the existential threat. AI can always-- - But how? Like enslaving us or turning us into paperclips? - I think the most compelling from the Sam Harris perspective would be the paperclip situation. - Yeah, I just think it's totally fanciful.
I mean, don't build a system. First of all, the code of engineering is you don't implement a system with massive control before testing it. Now, perhaps the culture of engineering will radically change, then I would worry, but I don't see any signs that engineers will suddenly do idiotic things, like put an electrical power plant in control of a system that they haven't tested first.
Or all of these scenarios not only imagine almost a magically powered intelligence, including things like cure cancer, which is probably an incoherent goal because there's so many different kinds of cancer, or bring about world peace. I mean, how do you even specify that as a goal? But the scenarios also imagine some degree of control of every molecule in the universe, which not only is itself unlikely, but we would not start to connect these systems to infrastructure without testing as we would any kind of engineering system.
Now, maybe some engineers will be irresponsible, and we need legal and regulatory and legal responsibility implemented so that engineers don't do things that are stupid by their own standards. But I've never seen enough of a plausible scenario of existential threat to devote large amounts of brain power to forestall it.
>>Corey: So you believe in the power en masse of the engineering of reason, as you argue in your latest book of Reason and Science, to be the very thing that guides the development of new technologies so it's safe and also keeps us safe. >>Kaiser: Yeah, if the same — granted, the same culture of safety that currently is part of the engineering mindset for airplanes, for example.
So yeah, I don't think that that should be thrown out the window and that untested, all-powerful systems should be suddenly implemented. But there's no reason to think they are. And in fact, if you look at the progress of artificial intelligence, it's been impressive, especially in the last 10 years or so.
But the idea that suddenly there'll be a step function, that all of a sudden, before we know it, it will be all-powerful, that there'll be some kind of recursive self-improvement, some kind of fume, is also fanciful. Certainly by the technology that now impresses us, such as deep learning, where you train something on hundreds of thousands or millions of examples, they're not hundreds of thousands of problems of which curing cancer is a typical example.
And so the kind of techniques that have allowed AI to increase in the last five years are not the kind that are going to lead to this fantasy of exponential, sudden self-improvement. >>Zubin: So — >>Kaiser: I think it's kind of a magical thinking. It's not based on our understanding of how AI actually works.
>>Zubin: Now, give me a chance here. So you said fanciful, magical thinking. In his TED Talk, Sam Harris says that thinking about AI killing all human civilization is somehow fun, intellectually. Now, I have to say, as a scientist and engineer, I don't find it fun. But when I'm having beer with my non-AI friends, there is indeed something fun and appealing about it.
Like talking about an episode of Black Mirror, considering if a large meteor is headed towards Earth — we were just told a large meteor is headed towards Earth, something like this. And can you relate to this sense of fun? And do you understand the psychology of it? >>Kaiser: Yes, right.
Good question. I personally don't find it fun. I find it kind of actually a waste of time, because there are genuine threats that we ought to be thinking about, like pandemics, like cybersecurity vulnerabilities, like the possibility of nuclear war, and certainly climate change. This is enough to fill many conversations.
And I think Sam did put his finger on something, namely that there is a community, sometimes called the rationality community, that delights in using its brainpower to come up with scenarios that would not occur to mere mortals, to less cerebral people. So there is a kind of intellectual thrill in finding new things to worry about that no one has worried about yet.
I actually think, though, that it's — not only is it a kind of fun that doesn't give me particular pleasure, but I think there can be a pernicious side to it, namely that you overcome people with such dread, such fatalism, that there's so many ways to die to annihilate our civilization, that we may as well enjoy life while we can.
There's nothing we can do about it. If climate change doesn't do us in, then runaway robots will. So let's enjoy ourselves now. We've got to prioritize. We have to look at threats that are close to certainty, such as climate change, and distinguish those from ones that are merely imaginable, but with infinitesimal probabilities.
And we have to take into account people's worry budget. You can't worry about everything. And if you sow dread and fear and terror and fatalism, it can lead to a kind of numbness. Well, these problems are overwhelming, and the engineers are just going to kill us all. So let's either destroy the entire infrastructure of science, technology, or let's just enjoy life while we can.
- So there's a certain line of worry, which I'm worried about a lot of things in engineering. There's a certain line of worry when you cross, you're allowed to cross, that it becomes paralyzing fear as opposed to productive fear. And that's kind of what you're highlighting. - Exactly right.
And we've seen some, we know that human effort is not well calibrated against risk in that, because a basic tenet of cognitive psychology is that perception of risk and hence perception of fear is driven by imaginability, not by data. And so we misallocate vast amounts of resources to avoiding terrorism, which kills on average about six Americans a year, with one exception of 9/11.
We invade countries, we invent entire new departments of government with massive, massive expenditure of resources and lives to defend ourselves against a trivial risk. Whereas guaranteed risks, you mentioned, as one of them is, you mentioned traffic fatalities, and even risks that are not here, but are plausible enough to worry about, like pandemics, like nuclear war, receive far too little attention.
In presidential debates, there's no discussion of how to minimize the risk of nuclear war. Lots of discussion of terrorism, for example. And so we, I think it's essential to calibrate our budget of fear, worry, concern planning to the actual probability of harm. - Yep. So let me ask this, then this question.
So speaking of imaginability, you said that it's important to think about reason. And one of my favorite people who likes to dip into the outskirts of reason through fascinating exploration of his imagination is Joe Rogan. - Oh, yes. - So who has, through reason, used to believe a lot of conspiracies, and through reason has stripped away a lot of his beliefs in that way.
So it's fascinating, actually, to watch him, through rationality, kind of throw away the ideas of Bigfoot and 9/11. I'm not sure exactly. - Kim Trails. I don't know what he believes in. Yes, okay. - But he no longer- - Believed in, no, that's right. - Believed in, that's right.
- No, he's become a real force for good. - Yep. So you were on the Joe Rogan podcast in February and had a fascinating conversation, but as far as I remember, didn't talk much about artificial intelligence. I will be on his podcast in a couple weeks. Joe is very much concerned about existential threat of AI.
I'm not sure if you're, which is why I was hoping that you would get into that topic. And in this way, he represents quite a lot of people who look at the topic of AI from 10,000 foot level. So as an exercise of communication, you said it's important to be rational and reason about these things.
Let me ask, if you were to coach me as an AI researcher about how to speak to Joe and the general public about AI, what would you advise? - Well, the short answer would be to read the sections that I wrote in Enlightenment, you know, about AI. But a longer reason would be, I think, to emphasize, and I think you're very well positioned as an engineer to remind people about the culture of engineering, that it really is safety oriented.
Another discussion in Enlightenment now, I plot rates of accidental death from various causes, plane crashes, car crashes, occupational accidents, even death by lightning strikes. And they all plummet because the culture of engineering is, how do you squeeze out the lethal risks? Death by fire, death by drowning, death by asphyxiation, all of them drastically declined because of advances in engineering, that I gotta say, I did not appreciate until I saw those graphs.
And it is because, exactly, people like you who stamp it and I think, oh my God, is what I'm inventing likely to hurt people? And to deploy ingenuity to prevent that from happening. Now, I'm not an engineer, although I spent 22 years at MIT, so I know something about the culture of engineering.
My understanding is that this is the way you think if you're an engineer. And it's essential that that culture not be suddenly switched off when it comes to artificial intelligence. So, I mean, that could be a problem, but is there any reason to think it would be switched off?
- I don't think so. And one, there's not enough engineers speaking up for this way, for the excitement, for the positive view of human nature, what you're trying to create is the positivity. Like everything we try to invent is trying to do good for the world. But let me ask you about the psychology of negativity.
It seems just objectively, not considering the topic, it seems that being negative about the future makes you sound smarter than being positive about the future, irregardless of topic. Am I correct in this observation? And if so, why do you think that is? - Yeah, I think there is that phenomenon that, as Tom Lehrer, the satirist said, "Always predict the worst and you'll be hailed as a prophet." It may be part of our overall negativity bias.
We are, as a species, more attuned to the negative than the positive. We dread losses more than we enjoy gains. And that might open up a space for prophets to remind us of harms and risks and losses that we may have overlooked. So I think there is that asymmetry.
- So you've written some of my favorite books all over the place. So starting from Enlightenment Now to The Better Angels of Our Nature, Blank Slate, How the Mind Works, the one about language, Language Instinct. Bill Gates, big fan too, said of your most recent book that it's my new favorite book of all time.
So for you as an author, what was the book early on in your life that had a profound impact on the way you saw the world? - Certainly this book, Enlightenment Now, is influenced by David Deutsch's The Beginning of Infinity. A rather deep reflection on knowledge and the power of knowledge to improve the human condition.
And with bits of wisdom such as that problems are inevitable, but problems are solvable given the right knowledge, and that solutions create new problems that have to be solved in their turn. That's, I think, a kind of wisdom about the human condition that influenced the writing of this book.
There's some books that are excellent but obscure, some of which I have on a page of my website. I read a book called The History of Force, self-published by a political scientist named James Paine on the historical decline of violence, and that was one of the inspirations for The Better Angels of Our Nature.
- What about early on? If you look back when you were maybe a teenager, is there some-- - I loved a book called One, Two, Three, Infinity. When I was a young adult, I read that book by George Gamow, the physicist. He had very accessible and humorous explanations of relativity, of number theory, of dimensionality, high multiple dimensional spaces, in a way that I think is still delightful 70 years after it was published.
I like the Time-Life Science series. These are books that arrive every month that my mother subscribed to, each one on a different topic. One would be on electricity, one would be on forests, one would be on evolution, and then one was on the mind. I was just intrigued that there could be a science of mind, and that book I would cite as an influence as well.
Then later on-- - That's when you fell in love with the idea of studying the mind? - That's one of the-- - Was that the thing that grabbed you? - It was one of the things, I would say. I read as a college student the book Reflections on Language by Noam Chomsky, who spent most of his career here at MIT.
Richard Dawkins, two books, The Blind Watchmaker and The Selfish Gene, were enormously influential, mainly for the content, but also for the writing style, the ability to explain abstract concepts in lively prose. Stephen Jay Gould's first collection, Ever Since Darwin, also an excellent example of lively writing. George Miller, a psychologist that most psychologists are familiar with, came up with the idea that human memory has a capacity of seven plus or minus two chunks.
That's probably his biggest claim to fame. But he wrote a couple of books on language and communication that I read as an undergraduate. Again, beautifully written and intellectually deep. - Wonderful. Stephen, thank you so much for taking the time today. - My pleasure. Thanks a lot, Lex. - Thanks.