I can tell chat GPT, create a piece of code, and then just run it on my computer. And I'm like, that sort of personalizes for me the what could possibly go wrong, so to speak. - Was that exciting or scary, that possibility? - It was a little bit scary actually, because it's kind of like, if you do that, what is the sandboxing that you should have?
And that's a version of that question for the world. That is, as soon as you put the AIs in charge of things, how many constraints should there be on these systems before you put the AIs in charge of all the weapons and all these different kinds of systems? - Well, here's the fun part about sandboxes, is the AI knows about them.
It has the tools to crack them. The following is a conversation with Stephen Wolfram, his fourth time on this podcast. He's a computer scientist, mathematician, theoretical physicist, and the founder of Wolfram Research, a company behind Mathematica, Wolfram Alpha, Wolfram Language, and the Wolfram Physics and Metamathematics projects. He has been a pioneer in exploring the computational nature of reality.
And so he's the perfect person to explore with together the new, quickly evolving landscape of large language models as human civilization journeys towards building super intelligent AGI. This is the Lex Friedman Podcast. To support it, please check out our sponsors in the description. And now, dear friends, here's Stephen Wolfram.
You announced the integration of Chad GPT and Wolfram Alpha and Wolfram Language. So let's talk about that integration. What are the key differences from the high philosophical level, maybe the technical level, between the capabilities of, broadly speaking, the two kinds of systems, large language models, and this computational, gigantic computational system infrastructure that is Wolfram Alpha?
- Yeah, so what does something like Chad GPT do? It's mostly focused on make language like the language that humans have made and put on the web and so on. So, you know, it's primary, sort of underlying technical thing is you've given a prompt, it's trying to continue that prompt in a way that's somehow typical of what it's seen based on a trillion words of text that humans have written on the web.
And the way it's doing that is with something which is probably quite similar to the way we humans do the first stages of that, using a neural net and so on, and just saying, given this piece of text, let's ripple through the neural net one word and get one word at a time of output.
And it's kind of a shallow computation on a large amount of kind of training data that is what we humans have put on the web. That's a different thing from sort of the computational stack that I spent the last, I don't know, 40 years or so building, which has to do with what can you compute many steps, potentially a very deep computation.
It's not sort of taking the statistics of what we humans have produced and trying to continue things based on that statistics. Instead, it's trying to take kind of the formal structure that we've created in our civilization, whether it's from mathematics or whether it's from kind of systematic knowledge of all kinds, and use that to do arbitrarily deep computations to figure out things that aren't just, let's match what's already been kind of said on the web, but let's potentially be able to compute something new and different that's never been computed before.
So as a practical matter, you know, what we're, our goal is to have made as much as possible of the world computable in the sense that if there's a question that in principle is answerable from some sort of expert knowledge that's been accumulated, we can compute the answer to that question, and we can do it in a sort of reliable way that's the best one can do given what the expertise that our civilization has accumulated.
It's a very, it's a much more sort of labor intensive on the side of kind of being creating kind of the computational system to do that. Obviously the, in the kind of the chat GPT world, it's like take things which were produced for quite other purposes, namely all the things we've written out on the web and so on and sort of forage from that things which are like what's been written on the web.
So I think, you know, as a practical point of view, I view sort of the chat GPT thing as being wide and shallow and what we're trying to do with sort of building out computation as being this sort of deep, also broad, but most importantly kind of deep type of thing.
I think another way to think about this is you go back in human history, you know, I don't know, thousand years or something, and you say, what can the typical person, what's the typical person going to figure out? Well, the answer is there's certain kinds of things that we humans can quickly figure out.
That's sort of what our, you know, at our neural architecture and the kinds of things we learn in our lives let us do. But then there's this whole layer of kind of formalization that got developed in which is, you know, the kind of whole sort of story of intellectual history and the whole kind of depth of learning, that formalization turned into things like logic, mathematics, science, and so on.
And that's the kind of thing that allows one to kind of build these towers of, of sort of towers of things you work out. It's not just, I can immediately figure this out. It's no, I can use this kind of formalism to go step by step and work out something which was not immediately obvious to me.
And that's kind of the story of what we're trying to do computationally is to be able to build those kind of tall towers of what implies what implies what and so on. And as opposed to kind of the, yes, I can immediately figure it out. It's just like what I saw somewhere else in something that I heard or remembered or something like this.
- What can you say about the kind of formal structure, the kind of formal foundation you can build such a formal structure on, about the kinds of things you would start on in order to build this kind of deep computable knowledge trees? - So the question is sort of, how do you think about computation?
And there's a couple of points here. One is what computation intrinsically is like. And the other is what aspects of computation we humans with our minds and with the kinds of things we've learned can sort of relate to in that computational universe. So if we start on the kind of what can computation be like, it's something I've spent some big chunk of my life studying is imagine that you're, we usually write programs where we kind of know what we want the program to do.
And we carefully write many lines of code and we hope that the program does what we intended it to do. But the thing I've been interested in is if you just look at the kind of natural science of programs, so you just say, I'm gonna make this program, it's a really tiny program.
Maybe I even pick the pieces of the program at random, but it's really tiny. And by really tiny, I mean, less than a line of code type thing. You say, what does this program do? And you run it. And big discovery that I made in the early 80s is that even extremely simple programs, when you run them can do really complicated things.
Really surprised me. It took me several years to kind of realize that that was a thing, so to speak. But that realization that even very simple programs can do incredibly complicated things that we very much don't expect. That discovery, I mean, I realized that that's very much, I think how nature works.
That is nature has simple rules, but yet does all sorts of complicated things that we might not expect. You know, a big thing of the last few years has been understanding that that's how the whole universe and physics works, but that's a quite separate topic. But so there's this whole world of programs and what they do and very rich, sophisticated things that these programs can do.
But when we look at many of these programs, we look at them and say, well, that's kind of, I don't really know what that's doing. It's not a very human kind of thing. So on the one hand, we have sort of what's possible in the computational universe. On the other hand, we have the kinds of things that we humans think about, the kinds of things that are developed in kind of our intellectual history.
And that's really the challenge to sort of making things computational is to connect what's computationally possible out in the computational universe with the things that we humans sort of typically think about with our minds. Now, that's a complicated kind of moving target because the things that we think about change over time.
We've learned more stuff. We've invented mathematics. We've invented various kinds of ideas and structures and so on. So it's gradually expanding. We're kind of gradually colonizing more and more of this kind of intellectual space of possibilities. But the real thing, the real challenge is how do you take what is computationally possible?
How do you take, how do you encapsulate the kinds of things that we think about in a way that kind of plugs in to what's computationally possible? And actually the big sort of idea there is this idea of kind of symbolic programming, symbolic representations of things. And so the question is, when you look at sort of everything in the world and you kind of take some visual scene or something you're looking at, and you say, well, how do I turn that into something that I can kind of stuff into my mind?
You know, there are lots of pixels in my visual scene, but the things that I remembered from that visual scene are, you know, there's a chair in this place. It's a kind of a symbolic representation of the visual scene. There are two chairs and a table or something, rather than there are all these pixels arranged in all these detailed ways.
And so the question then is how do you take sort of all the things in the world and make some kind of representation that corresponds to the types of ways that we think about things? And human language is sort of one form of representation that we have. We talk about chairs, that's a word in human language and so on.
How do we take, but human language is not in and of itself something that plugs in very well to sort of computation. It's not something from which you can immediately compute consequences and so on. And so you have to kind of find a way to take sort of the stuff we understand from human language and make it more precise.
And that's really the story of symbolic programming. And you know, what that turns into is something which I didn't know at the time it was going to work as well as it has. But back in the 1979 or so, I was trying to build my first big computer system and trying to figure out, you know, how should I represent computations at a high level?
And I kind of invented this idea of using kind of symbolic expressions, you know, structured as it's kind of like a function and a bunch of arguments, but that function doesn't necessarily evaluate to anything. It's just a thing that sits there representing a structure. And so building up that structure, and it's turned out that structure has been extremely, it's a good match for the way that we humans, it seems to be a good match for the way that we humans kind of conceptualize higher level things.
And it's been for the last, I don't know, 45 years or something, it's served me remarkably well. - So building up that structure using this kind of symbolic representation. But what can you say about abstractions here? Because you could just start with your physics project, you could start at a hypergraph at a very, very low level and build up everything from there, but you don't.
You take shortcuts. - Right. - You take the highest level of abstraction, convert that, the kind of abstraction that's convertible to something computable using symbolic representation. And then that's your new foundation for that little piece of knowledge. Somehow all of that is integrated. - Right, so the sort of a very important phenomenon that is kind of a thing that I've sort of realized is just, it's one of these things that sort of in the future of kind of everything is going to become more and more important as this phenomenon of computational irreducibility.
And the question is, if you know the rules for something, you have a program, you're gonna run it, you might say, I know the rules, great. I know everything about what's gonna happen. Well, in principle you do, because you can just run those rules out and just see what they do.
You might run them a million steps, you see what happens, et cetera. The question is, can you like immediately jump ahead and say, I know what's gonna happen after a million steps and the answer is 13 or something. And one of the very critical things to realize is if you could reduce that computation, there is in a sense, no point in doing the computation.
The place where you really get value out of doing the computation is when you had to do the computation to find out the answer. But this phenomenon that you have to do the computation to find out the answer, this phenomenon of computational irreducibility seems to be tremendously important for thinking about lots of kinds of things.
So one of the things that happens is, okay, you've got a model of the universe at the low level in terms of atoms of space and hypergraphs and rewriting hypergraphs and so on. And it's happening 10 to the 100 times every second, let's say, well, you say, great, then we've nailed it.
We know how the universe works. Well, the problem is the universe can figure out what it's gonna do. It does those 10 to the 100 steps. But for us to work out what it's gonna do, we have no way to reduce that computation. The only way to do the computation, to see the result of the computation is to do it.
And if we're operating within the universe, we're kind of, there's no opportunity to do that 'cause the universe is doing it as fast as the universe can do it. And that's what's happening. So what we're trying to do, and a lot of the story of science and a lot of other kinds of things is finding pockets of reducibility.
That is, you could have a situation where everything in the world is full of computational irreducibility. We never know what's gonna happen next. The only way we can figure out what's gonna happen next is just let the system run and see what happens. So in a sense, the story of most kinds of science, inventions, a lot of kinds of things is the story of finding these places where we can locally jump ahead.
And one of the features of computational irreducibility is there are always pockets of reducibility. There are always places, there are always an infinite number of places where you can jump ahead. There's no way where you can jump completely ahead, but there are little patches, little places where you can jump ahead a bit.
And I think, we can talk about physics project and so on, but I think the thing we realize is we kind of exist in a slice of all the possible computational irreducibility in the universe. We exist in a slice where there's a reasonable amount of predictability. And in a sense, as we try and construct these kind of higher levels of abstraction, symbolic representations and so on, what we're doing is we're finding these lumps of reducibility that we can kind of attach ourselves to and about which we can kind of have fairly simple narrative things to say.
Because in principle, I say, what's gonna happen in the next few seconds? Oh, there are these molecules moving around in the air in this room, and oh gosh, it's an incredibly complicated story. And that's a whole computationally irreducible thing, most of which I don't care about. And most of it is, well, the air is still gonna be here and nothing much is going to be different about it.
And that's a kind of reducible fact about what is ultimately at an underlying level of computationally irreducible process. - And life would not be possible if we didn't have a large number of such reducible pockets. - Yes. - And that's amenable to reduction into something symbolic. - Yes, I think so.
I mean, life in the way that we experience it, that, I mean, one might, depending on what we mean by life, so to speak, the experience that we have of sort of consistent things happening in the world, the idea of space, for example, where there's, we can just say, you're here, you move there.
It's kind of the same thing. It's still you in that different place, even though you're made of different atoms of space and so on. This idea that there's sort of this level of predictability of what's going on, that's us finding a slice of reducibility in what is underneath this computationally irreducible kind of system.
And I think that's sort of the thing, which is actually my favorite discovery of the last few years, is the realization that it is sort of the interaction between the sort of underlying computational irreducibility and our nature as kind of observers who sort of have to key into computational reducibility.
That fact leads to the main laws of physics that we discovered in the 20th century. So this is, we talk about this in more detail, but this is, to me, it's kind of our nature as observers, the fact that we are computationally bounded observers, we don't get to follow all those little pieces of computational irreducibility.
To stuff what is out there in the world into our minds requires that we are looking at things that are reducible, we are compressing, kind of we're extracting just some essence, some kind of symbolic essence of what's the detail of what's going on in the world. That together with one other condition that at first seems sort of trivial, but isn't, which is that we believe we are persistent in time.
That is, you know-- - So that's the causality. - Here's the thing, at every moment, according to our theory, we're made of different atoms of space. At every moment, sort of the microscopic detail of what the universe is made of is being rewritten. And that's, and in fact, the very fact that there's coherence between different parts of space is a consequence of the fact that there are all these little processes going on that kind of knit together the structure of space.
It's kind of like if you wanted to have a fluid with a bunch of molecules in it, if those molecules weren't interacting, you wouldn't have this fluid that would pour and do all these kinds of things. It would just be sort of a free-floating collection of molecules. So similarly it is with space, that the fact that space is kind of knitted together is a consequence of all this activity in space.
And the fact that kind of what we consist of sort of this series of, you know, we're continually being rewritten. And the question is, why is it the case that we think of ourselves as being the same us through time? That's kind of a key assumption. I think it's a key aspect of what we see as sort of our consciousness, so to speak, is that we have this kind of consistent thread of experience.
- Well, isn't that just another limitation of our mind that we want to reduce reality into some, that kind of temporal consistency is just a nice narrative to tell ourselves. - Well, the fact is, I think it's critical to the way we humans typically operate is that we have a single thread of experience.
You know, if you imagine sort of a mind where you have, you know, maybe that's what's happening in various kinds of minds that aren't working the same way other minds work, is that you're splitting into multiple threads of experience. It's also something where, you know, when you look at, I don't know, quantum mechanics, for example, in the insides of quantum mechanics, it's splitting into many threads of experience.
But in order for us humans to interact with it, you kind of have to knit all those different threads together so that we say, oh yeah, a definite thing happened, and now the next definite thing happens, and so on. And I think, you know, sort of inside, it's sort of interesting to try and imagine what's it like to have kind of these fundamentally multiple threads of experience going on.
I mean, right now, different human minds have different threads of experience. We just have a bunch of minds that are interacting with each other, but we don't have a, you know, within each mind, there's a single thread. And that is indeed a simplification. I think it's a thing, you know, the general computational system does not have that simplification.
And it's one of the things, you know, people often seem to think that, you know, consciousness is the highest level of kind of things that can happen in the universe, so to speak, but I think that's not true. I think it's actually a specialization in which, among other things, you have this idea of a single thread of experience, which is not a general feature of anything that could kind of computationally happen in the universe.
- So it's a feature of a computationally limited system that's only able to observe reducible pockets. So, I mean, this word observer, it means something in quantum mechanics. It means something in a lot of places. It means something to us humans as conscious beings. So what's the importance of the observer?
What is the observer and what's the importance of the observer in the computational universe? - So this question of what is an observer, what's the general idea of an observer, is actually one of my next projects, which got somewhat derailed by the current sort of AI mania, but-- - Is there a connection there, or is that, do you think the observer is primarily a physics phenomenon?
Is it related to the whole AI thing? - Yes. - Yes, it is related. So one question is what is a general observer? So, we know, we have an idea what is a general computational system. We think about Turing machines, we think about other models of computation. There's a question, what is a general model of an observer?
And there's kind of observers like us, which is kind of the observers we're interested in. We could imagine an alien observer that deals with computational irreducibility, and it has a mind that's utterly different from ours and completely incoherent with what we're like. But the fact is that if we are talking about observers like us, that one of the key things is this idea of kind of taking all the detail of the world and being able to stuff it into a mind, being able to take all the detail and kind of extract out of it a smaller set of kind of degrees of freedom, a smaller number of elements that will sort of fit in our minds.
And I think this question, so I've been interested in trying to characterize what is the general observer? And the general observer is, I think, in part, there are many, let me give an example of it. You know, you have a gas, it's got a bunch of molecules bouncing around, and the thing you're measuring about the gas is its pressure.
And the only thing you as an observer care about is pressure. And that means you have a piston on the side of this box, and the piston is being pushed by the gas. And there are many, many different ways that molecules can hit that piston. But all that matters is the kind of aggregate of all those molecular impacts, 'cause that's what determines pressure.
So there's a huge number of different configurations of the gas, which are all equivalent. So I think one key aspect of observers is this equivalency of many different configurations of a system saying, "All I care about is this aggregate feature. All I care about is this overall thing." And that's sort of one aspect.
And we see that in lots of different, again, it's the same story over and over again, that there's a lot of detail in the world, but what we are extracting from it is something, a sort of a thin summary of that detail. - Is that thin summary nevertheless true?
Can it be a crappy approximation? - Sure. - That on average is correct? I mean, if we look at the observer that's the human mind, it seems like there's a lot of very, as represented by natural language, for example, there's a lot of really crappy approximation. - Sure. - And that could be maybe a feature of it.
- Well, yes. - But there's ambiguity. - Right, right. You don't know, it could be the case. You're just measuring the aggregate impacts of these molecules, but there is some tiny, tiny probability that molecules will arrange themselves in some really funky way. And that just measuring that average isn't going to be the main point.
By the way, an awful lot of science is very confused about this. Because you look at papers and people are really keen, they draw this curve and they have these bars on the curve and things. It's just this curve. And it's this one thing. And it's supposed to represent some system that has all kinds of details in it.
And this is a way that lots of science has gotten wrong. Because people say, I remember years ago I was studying snowflake growth. You have a snowflake and it's growing, it has all these arms, it's doing complicated things. But there was a literature on this stuff and it talked about what's the rate of snowflake growth.
And it got pretty good answers for the rate of the growth of the snowflake. And I looked at it more carefully and they had these nice curves of snowflake growth rates and so on. I looked at it more carefully and I realized, according to their models, the snowflake will be spherical.
And so they got the growth rate right, but the detail was just utterly wrong. And not only the detail, the whole thing was not capturing, it was capturing this aspect of the system that was in a sense missing the main point of what was going on. - What is the geometric shape of a snowflake?
- Snowflakes start in the phase of water that's relevant to formation of snowflakes. It's a phase of ice which starts with a hexagonal arrangement of water molecules. And so it starts off growing as a hexagonal plate. And then what happens is-- - It's a plate, oh, oh, versus sphere, sphere versus plate.
- Well, no, no, but it's much more than that. I mean, snowflakes are fluffy. Typical snowflakes have little dendritic arms. And what actually happens is, it's kind of cool because you can make these very simple discrete models with cellular automata and things that figure this out. You start off with this hexagonal thing, and then the places, it starts to grow little arms.
And every time a little piece of ice adds itself to the snowflake, the fact that that ice condensed from the water vapor heats the snowflake up locally. And so it makes it less likely for another piece of ice to accumulate right nearby. So this leads to a kind of growth inhibition.
So you grow an arm and it is a separated arm because right around the arm, it got a little bit hot and it didn't add more ice there. So what happens is it grows, you have a hexagon, it grows out arms, the arms grow arms, and then the arms grow arms, grow arms.
And eventually, actually, it's kind of cool because it actually fills in another hexagon, a bigger hexagon. And when I first looked at this, I had a very simple model for this. I realized when it fills in that hexagon, it actually leaves some holes behind. So I thought, well, is that really right?
So I look at these pictures of snowflakes and sure enough, they have these little holes in them that are kind of scars of the way that these arms grow out. - So you can't fill in backfill holes. So it just keeps going up. - They don't backfill, yeah. They don't backfill.
- And presumably, there's a limitation of how big, like you can't arbitrarily grow. - I'm not sure. I mean, the thing falls through the, I mean, I think it hits the ground at some point. I think you can grow, I think you can grow in the lab. I think you can grow pretty big ones.
I think you can grow many, many iterations of this kind of, goes from hexagon, it grows out arms, it turns back, it fills back into a hexagon, it grows more arms again. - In 3D. - No, it's flat, usually. - Why is it flat? Why doesn't it span out?
Okay, okay, okay, wait a minute. You said it's fluffy, and fluffy is a three-dimensional property, no? - No, it's fluffy. Snow is, okay, so what makes, we're really in a detail. - I like this, let's go there. There's multiple snowflakes become fluffy. Well, a single snowflake is not fluffy.
- No, no, a single snowflake is fluffy. And what happens is, if you have snow that is just pure hexagons, they fit together pretty well. It doesn't have a lot of air in it. And they can also slide against each other pretty easily. And so the snow can be pretty, I think avalanches happen sometimes when the things tend to be these hexagonal plates, and it kind of slides.
But then when the thing has all these arms that have grown out, they don't fit together very well. And that's why the snow has lots of air in it. And if you look at one of these snowflakes, and if you catch one, you'll see it has these little arms.
And people, actually people often say, no two snowflakes are alike. That's mostly because as a snowflake grows, they do grow pretty consistently with these different arms and so on. But you capture them at different times. As they fell through the air in a different way, you'll catch this one at this stage.
And as it goes through different stages, they look really different. And so that's why it kind of looks like no two snowflakes are alike, because you caught them at different times. - So the rules under which they grow are the same. It's just the timing is. - Yes. - Okay, so the point is, science is not able to describe the full complexity of snowflake growth.
- Well, science, if you do what people might often do, which is say, okay, let's make it scientific. Let's turn it into one number. And that one number is kind of the growth rate of the arms or some such other thing. That fails to capture sort of the detail of what's going on inside the system.
And that's in a sense a big challenge for science, is how do you extract from the natural world, for example, those aspects of it that you are interested in talking about? Now, you might just say, I don't really care about the fluffiness of the snowflakes. All I care about is the growth rate of the arms, in which case, you can have a good model without knowing anything about the fluffiness.
But the fact is, as a practical, if you say, what is the most obvious feature of a snowflake? Oh, that it has this complicated shape. Well, then you've got a different story about what you model. I mean, this is one of the features of sort of modeling in science.
That what is a model? A model is some way of reducing the actuality of the world to something where you can readily sort of give a narrative for what's happening, where you can basically make some kind of abstraction of what's happening and answer questions that you care about answering.
If you wanted to answer all possible questions about the system, you'd have to have the whole system, 'cause you might care about this particular molecule. Where did it go? And your model, which is some big abstraction of that, has nothing to say about that. So, one of the things that's often confusing in science is people will have, I've got a model, somebody says.
Somebody else will say, I don't believe in your model because it doesn't capture the feature of the system that I care about. There's always this controversy about, is it a correct model? Well, no model is, except for the actual system itself, is a correct model in the sense that it captures everything.
Question is, does it capture what you care about capturing? Sometimes that's ultimately defined by what you're going to build technology out of, things like this. The one counterexample to this is, if you think you're modeling the whole universe all the way down, then there is a notion of a correct model.
But even that is more complicated because it depends on kind of how observers sample things and so on, that's a separate story. But at least at the first level, to say, this thing about, oh, it's an approximation, you're capturing one aspect, you're not capturing other aspects. When you really think you have a complete model for the whole universe, you better be capturing ultimately everything, even though to actually run that model is impossible because of computational irreducibility.
The only thing that successfully runs that model is the actual running of the universe. - Is the universe itself. But okay, so what you care about is an interesting concept. So that's a human concept. So that's what you're doing with Wolfram Alpha and Wolfram Language, is you're trying to come up with symbolic representations as simple as possible.
So a model that's as simple as possible that fully captures stuff we care about. - Yes, so I mean, for example, we could, we'll have a thing about data about movies, let's say. We could be describing every individual pixel in every movie and so on, but that's not the level that people care about.
And it's, yes, this is a, I mean, and that level that people care about is somewhat related to what's described in natural language. But what we're trying to do is to find a way to sort of represent precisely so you can compute things. See, one thing we say, you give a piece of natural language, question is you feed it to a computer.
You say, does the computer understand this natural language? Well, the computer processes it in some way, it does this, maybe it can make a continuation of the natural language. Maybe it can go on from the prompt and say what it's gonna say. You say, does it really understand it?
Hard to know, but for in this kind of computational world, there is a very definite definition of does it understand, which is, could it be turned into this symbolic computational thing from which you can compute all kinds of consequences? And that's the sense in which one has sort of a target for the understanding of natural language.
And that's kind of our goal is to have as much as possible about the world that can be computed in a reasonable way, so to speak, be able to be sort of captured by this kind of computational language. That's kind of the goal. And I think for us humans, the main thing that's important is as we formalize what we're talking about, it gives us a way of kind of building a structure where we can sort of build this tower of consequences of things.
So if we're just saying, well, let's talk about it in natural language, it doesn't really give us some hard foundation that lets us build step by step to work something out. I mean, it's kind of like what happens in math. If we were just sort of vaguely talking about math, but didn't have the kind of full structure of math and all that kind of thing, we wouldn't be able to build this kind of big tower of consequences.
And so, in a sense, what we're trying to do with the whole computational language effort is to make a formalism for describing the world that makes it possible to kind of build this tower of consequences. - Well, can you talk about this dance between natural language and Wolfram language?
So there's this gigantic thing called the internet where people post memes and diary type thoughts and very important sounding articles and all of that that makes up the training data set for GPT. And then there's Wolfram language. How can you map from the natural language of the internet to the Wolfram language?
Is there a manual, is there an automated way of doing that as we look into the future? - Well, so Wolfram Alpha, what it does, its kind of front end is turning natural language into computational language. - What you mean by that is there's a prompt, you ask a question, what is the capital of some country?
- And it turns into, what's the distance between Chicago and London or something? And that will turn into geo distance of entity, city, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. Each one of those things is very well defined. We know, given that it's the entity, city, Chicago, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera, Illinois, United States, we know the geo location of that, we know its population, we know all kinds of things about it, which we have curated that data to be able to know that with some degree of certainty, so to speak.
And then we can compute things from this. And that's kind of the, yeah, that's the idea. - But then something like GPT, large language models, do they allow you to make that conversion much more powerful? - Okay, so that's an interesting thing, which we still don't know everything about, okay?
I mean, this question of going from natural language to computational language, in Wolfram Alpha, we've now, Wolfram Alpha's been out and about for what, 13 and a half years now. And we've achieved, I don't know what it is, 98%, 99% success on queries that get put into it. Now, obviously, there's a sort of feedback loop 'cause the things that work are things people go on putting into it.
So that, but we've got to a very high success rate of the little fragments of natural language that people put in, questions, math calculations, chemistry calculations, whatever it is. We do very well at that, turning those things into computational language. Now, from the very beginning of Wolfram Alpha, I thought about, for example, writing code with natural language.
In fact, I had, I was just looking at this recently, I had a post that I wrote in 2010, 2011, called something like programming with natural language is actually going to work, okay? And so, we had done a bunch of experiments using methods that were a little bit, some of them a little bit machine learning-like, but certainly not the same kind of idea of vast training data and so on that is the story of large language models.
Actually, I know that post, a piece of utter trivia, but that post, Steve Jobs forwarded that post around to all kinds of people at Apple. And he, you know, that was, 'cause he never really liked programming languages. So he was very happy to see the idea that you could get rid of this kind of layer of kind of engineering-like structure.
He would have liked, you know, I think what's happening now because it really is the case that you can, you know, this idea that you have to kind of learn how the computer works to use a programming language is something that is, I think, a thing that, you know, just like you had to learn the details of the opcodes to know how assembly language worked and so on.
It's kind of a thing that's a limited time horizon, but kind of the, you know, so this idea of how elaborate can you make kind of the prompt, how elaborate can you make the natural language and abstract from it computational language? It's a very interesting question. And, you know, what chat-GBT, you know, GBT-4 and so on can do is pretty good.
It isn't, it's a very interesting process. I mean, I'm still trying to understand this workflow. We've been working out a lot of tooling around this workflow. - The natural language to computational language. - Right. - And the process, especially if it's conversation, like dialogue, it's like multiple queries kind of thing.
- Yeah, right. There's so many things that are really interesting that work and so on. So first thing is, can you just walk up to the computer and expect to sort of specify a computation? What one realizes is humans have to have some idea of kind of this way of thinking about things computationally.
Without that, you're kind of out of luck because you just have no idea what you're going to walk up to a computer. - I remember when I should tell a silly story about myself. The very first computer I saw, which is when I was 10 years old, and it was a big mainframe computer and so on.
And I didn't really understand what computers did. And it's like, somebody was showing me this computer and it's like, you know, can the computer work out the weight of a dinosaur? It's like, that isn't a sensible thing to ask. That's kind of, you know, you have to give it, that's not what computers do.
I mean, in Wolfram Alpha, for example, you could say, what's the typical weight of a stegosaurus? And it will give you some answer, but that's a very different kind of thing from what one thinks of computers as doing. And so the kind of the question of, you know, first thing is people have to have an idea of what computation is about.
And, you know, I think it's a very, you know, for education, that is the key thing. It's kind of this notion, not computer science, not sort of the details of programming, but just this idea of how do you think about the world computationally. Computation, thinking about the world computationally is kind of this formal way of thinking about the world.
We've had other ones like logic was a formal way, you know, as a way of sort of abstracting and formalizing some aspects of the world. Mathematics is another one. Computation is this very broad way of sort of formalizing the way we think about the world. And the thing that's cool about computation is if we can successfully formalize things in terms of computation, computers can help us figure out what the consequences are.
It's not like you formalized it with math. Well, that's nice, but now you have to, if you're not using a computer to do the math, you have to go work out a bunch of stuff yourself. So I think, but this idea, let's see, I mean, that we're trying to take kind of the, we're talking about sort of natural language and its relationship to computational language.
The thing, the sort of the typical workflow, I think is first human has to have some kind of idea of what they're trying to do. That if it's something that they want to sort of build a tower of capabilities on, something that they want to sort of formalize and make computational.
So then human can type something into, you know, some LLM system and sort of say vaguely what they want in sort of computational terms. Then it does pretty well at synthesizing well from language code. And it'll probably do better in the future 'cause we've got a huge number of examples of natural language input together with the Wolfram language translation of that.
So it's kind of a, you know, that's a thing where you can kind of extrapolating from all those examples makes it easier to do that task. - Is the prompter task could also kind of debugging the Wolfram language code? Or is your hope to not do that debugging? - Oh, no, no, no.
I mean, so there are many steps here. Okay, so first, the first thing is you type natural language. It generates Wolfram language code. - Do you have examples by the way? Do you have an example that is the dinosaur example? Do you have an example that jumps to mind that we should be thinking about some dumb example?
- It's like take my heart rate data and, you know, figure out whether I, you know, make a moving average every seven days or something and work out what the, and make a plot of the results. Okay, so that's a thing which is, you know, about two thirds of a line of Wolfram language code.
I mean, it's, you know, list plot of moving average of some data bin or something of the data and then you'll get the result. And, you know, the vague thing that I was just saying in natural language could, would almost certainly correctly turn into that very simple piece of Wolfram language code.
- So you start mumbling about heart rate. - Yeah. - And then kind of, you know, you arrive at the moving average kind of idea. - Right, you say average over seven days, maybe it'll figure out that that's a moving, you know, that that can be encapsulated as this moving average idea.
I'm not sure. But then the typical workflow that I'm seeing is you generate this piece of Wolfram language code. It's pretty small usually. It's, and if it isn't small, it probably isn't right. But, you know, if it's, it's pretty small and, you know, Wolfram language is, one of the ideas of Wolfram language is it's a language that humans can read.
It's not a language which, you know, programming languages tend to be this one way story of humans write them and computers execute from them. Wolfram language is intended to be something which is sort of like math notation, something where, you know, humans write it and humans are supposed to read it as well.
And so kind of the workflow that's emerging is kind of this, this human mumbles some things, you know, large language model produces a fragment of Wolfram language code. Then you look at that, you say, yeah, that looks, well, typically you just run it first. You see, does it produce the right thing?
You look at what it produces. You might say, that's obviously crazy. You look at the code, you see, I see why it's crazy. You fix it. If you really care about the result and you really want to make sure it's right, you better look at that code and understand it because that's the way you have the sort of checkpoint of did it really do what I expected it to do?
Now you go beyond that. I mean, it's, it's, it's, you know, what we find is, for example, let's say the code does the wrong thing. Then you can often say to the large language model, can you adjust this to do this? And it's pretty good at doing that. - Interesting.
So you're using the output of the code to give you hints about the, the function of the code. So you're debugging based on the output of the code, not the code itself. - Right. The plugin that we have, you know, for chat GPT, it does that routinely. You know, it will send the thing in, it will get a result.
It will discover, the LLM will discover itself that the result is not plausible. And it will go back and say, oh, I'm sorry. It's very polite. And it, you know, it goes back and says, I'll rewrite that piece of code and then it will try it again and get the result.
The other thing that's pretty interesting is when you're just running. So one of the new concepts that we have, we invented this whole idea of notebooks back 36 years ago now. And so now there's the question of sort of how do you combine this idea of notebooks where you have, you know, text and code and output?
How do you combine that with the notion of chat and so on? And there's some really interesting things there. Like for example, a very typical thing now is we have these notebooks where as soon as the, if the thing produces errors, if the, you know, run this code and it produces messages and so on, the LLM automatically not only looks at those messages, it can also see all kinds of internal information about stack traces and things like this.
And it can then, it does a remarkably good job of guessing what's wrong and telling you. So in other words, it's looking at things, sort of interesting. It's kind of a typical sort of AI-ish thing that it's able to have more sensory data than we humans are able to have.
'Cause it's able to look at a bunch of stuff that we humans would kind of glaze over looking at. And it's able to then come up with, oh, this is the explanation of what's happening. - And what is the data, the stack trace, the code you've written previously, the natural language you've written?
- Yeah, it's also what's happening is, one of the things that's, is for example, when there's these messages, there's documentation about these messages. There's examples of where the messages have occurred. Otherwise, all these kinds of things. The other thing that's really amusing with this is when it makes a mistake, one of the things that's in our prompt when the code doesn't work is read the documentation.
(laughing) And we have another piece of the plugin that lets it read documentation. And that again, is very, very useful. 'Cause it will figure out, sometimes it'll get, it'll make up the name of some option for some function that doesn't really exist, read the documentation. It'll have some wrong structure for the function and so on.
It's some, that's a powerful thing. I mean, the thing that I've realized is, we built this language over the course of all these years to be nice and coherent and consistent and so on. So it's easy for humans to understand. Turns out there was a side effect that I didn't anticipate, which is it makes it easier for AIs to understand.
- So it's almost like another natural language. But so Wolfram language is a kind of foreign language. - Yes, yes. - You have a lineup, English, French, Japanese, Wolfram language, and then, I don't know, Spanish. And then the system is not gonna notice, hopefully. - Well, yes. I mean, maybe.
You know, that's an interesting question. 'Cause it really depends on what I see as being an important piece of fundamental science that basically just jumped out at us with Chachapiti. 'Cause I think, you know, the real question is, why does Chachapiti work? How is it possible to encapsulate, you know, to successfully reproduce all these kinds of things in natural language, you know, with a, you know, a comparatively small, he says, you know, couple of hundred billion, you know, weights of neural net and so on.
And I think that, you know, that relates to kind of a fundamental fact about language, which, you know, the main thing is that I think there's a structure to language that we haven't kind of really explored very well, it's kind of the semantic grammar I'm talking about language. I mean, we kind of know that when we set up human language, we know that it has certain regularities.
We know that it has a certain grammatical structure, you know, noun followed by verb, followed by noun, adjectives, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. That's its kind of grammatical structure. But I think the thing that Chachapiti is showing us is that there's an additional kind of regularity to language, which has to do with the meaning of the language beyond just this pure, you know, part of speech combination type of thing.
And I think the kind of the one example of that that we've had in the past is logic. And, you know, I think my sort of kind of picture of how was logic invented, how was logic discovered? It really was the thing that was discovered in its original conception.
It was discovered presumably by Aristotle, who kind of listened to a bunch of people, orators, you know, giving speeches, and this one made sense, that one doesn't make sense, this one, and, you know, you see these patterns of, you know, if the, you know, I don't know what, you know, if the Persians do this, then the this does that, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.
And what Aristotle realized is there's a structure to those sentences, there's a structure to that rhetoric that doesn't matter whether it's the Persians and the Greeks or whether it's the cats and the dogs. It's just, you know, P and Q, you can abstract from the details of these particular sentences, you can lift out this kind of formal structure, and that's what logic is.
- That's a heck of a discovery, by the way, logic, you're making me realize now. - Yeah. - It's not obvious. - The fact that there is an abstraction from natural language that has, where you can fill in any word you want. - Yeah. - Is a very interesting discovery.
Now, it took a long time to mature. I mean, Aristotle had this idea of syllogistic logic, where there were these particular patterns of how you could argue things, so to speak. And, you know, in the Middle Ages, part of education was you memorized the syllogisms, I forget how many there were, but 15 of them or something.
And they all had names, they all had mnemonics, like I think Barbara and Sellerant were two of the mnemonics for the syllogisms. And people would kind of, this is a valid argument 'cause it follows the Barbara syllogism, so to speak. And it took until 1830, you know, with George Boole to kind of get beyond that and kind of see that there was a level of abstraction that was beyond this particular template of a sentence, so to speak.
And that's, you know, what's interesting there is, in a sense, you know, chat-GBT is operating at the Aristotelian level. It's essentially dealing with templates of sentences. By the time you get to Boole and Boolean algebra and this idea of, you know, you can have arbitrary depth nested collections of ands and ors and nots, and you can resolve what they mean, that's the kind of thing, that's a computation story.
That's, you know, you've gone beyond the pure sort of templates of natural language to something which is an arbitrarily deep computation. But the thing that I think we realized from chat-GBT is, you know, Aristotle stopped too quickly. And there was more that you could have lifted out of language as formal structures.
And I think there's, you know, in a sense, we've captured some of that in, you know, some of what is in language, there's a lot of kind of little calculi, little algebras of what you can say, what language talks about. I mean, whether it's, I don't know, if you say, I go from place A to place B, place B to place C, then I know I've gone from place A to place C.
If A is a friend of B and B is a friend of C, it doesn't necessarily follow that A is a friend of C. These are things that are, you know, that there are, if you go from place A to place B, place B to place C, it doesn't matter how you went.
Like logic, it doesn't matter whether you flew there, walked there, swam there, whatever. You still, this transitivity of where you go is still valid. And there are many kinds of kind of features, I think, of the way the world works that are captured in these aspects of language, so to speak.
And I think what "Chat GPT" effectively has found, just like it discovered logic, you know, people are really surprised it can do these logical inferences. It discovered logic the same way Aristotle discovered logic, by looking at a lot of sentences, effectively, and noticing the patterns in those sentences. - But it feels like it's discovering something much more complicated than logic.
So this kind of semantic grammar, I think you wrote about this, maybe we can call it the laws of language, I believe you call, or which I like, the laws of thought. - Yes, that was the title that George Boole had for his Boolean algebra back in 1830, but yes.
- Laws of thought? - Yes, that was what he said. - Ooh. - All right. - So he thought he nailed it with Boolean algebra. - Yeah. - There's more to it. - And it's a good question, how much more is there to it? And it seems like one of the reasons, as you imply that the reason "Chat GPT" works is that there's a finite number of things to it.
- Yeah, I mean, it's-- - It's discovering the laws, in some sense, GPT's discovering the laws of semantic grammar that underlies language. - Yes, and what's sort of interesting is, in the computational universe, there's a lot of other kinds of computation that you could do. They're just not ones that we humans have cared about and operate with, and that's probably because our brains are built in a certain way, and the neural nets of our brains are not that different, in some sense, from the neural nets of a large language model, and that's kind of, and so when we think about, and maybe you can talk about this some more, but when we think about sort of what will AIs ultimately do, the answer is, insofar as AIs are just doing computation, they can run off and do all these kinds of crazy computations, but the ones that we sort of have, have decided we care about is this kind of very limited set.
- That's where the reinforcement learning with human feedback seems to come in. The more the AIs say the stuff that kind of interests us, the more we're impressed by it. So it can do a lot of interesting, intelligent things, but we're only interested in the AI systems when they communicate in a human-like way about human-like topics.
- Yes, well, it's like technology. I mean, in a sense, the physical world provides all kinds of things. You know, there are all kinds of processes going on in physics. Only a limited set of those are ones that we capture and use for technology, 'cause they're only a limited set where we say, you know, this is a thing that we can sort of apply to the human purposes we currently care about.
I mean, you might've said, okay, you pick up a piece of rock. You say, okay, this is a nice silicate. It contains all kinds of silicon. I don't care. Then you realize, oh, we could actually turn this into a semiconductor wafer and make a microprocessor out of it. And then we care a lot about it.
- Yes. - And it's, you know, it's this thing about what do we, you know, in the evolution of our civilization, what things do we identify as being things we care about? I mean, it's like, you know, when there was a little announcement recently of the possibility of a high temperature superconductor that involved, you know, the element lutetium, which, you know, generally nobody has cared about.
(Lex laughing) And, you know, it's kind of, but suddenly if there's this application that relates to kind of human purposes, we start to care a lot. - So given your thinking that GPT may have discovered inklings of laws of thought, do you think such laws exist? Can we linger on that?
- Yeah. - What's your intuition here? - Oh, definitely. I mean, the fact is, look, the logic is but the first step. There are many other kinds of calculi about things that we consider, you know, about sort of things that happen in the world or things that are meaningful.
- Well, how do you know logic is not the last step? You know what I mean? So like what- - Well, because we can plainly see that that thing, I mean, if you say, here's a sentence that is syntactically correct, okay? You look at it and you're like, you know, the happy electron, you know, ate, I don't know what, some something that it just, you look at it and it's like, this is meaningless.
It's just a bunch of words. It's syntactically correct. The nouns and the verbs are in the right place, but it just doesn't mean anything. And so there clearly is some rule that there are rules that determine when a sentence has the potential to be meaningful that go beyond the pure parts of speech syntax.
And so the question is, what are those rules? And are there a fairly finite set of those rules? My guess is that there's a fairly finite set of those rules. And they, you know, once you have those rules, you have a kind of a construction kit, just like the rules of syntactic grammar give you a construction kit for making syntactically correct sentences.
So you can also have a construction kit for making semantically correct sentences. Those sentences may not be realized in the world. I mean, I think, you know, the elephant flew to the moon. - Yeah. - A syntactically, a semantically, you know, we know, we have an idea. If I say that to you, you kind of know what that means.
But the fact is it hasn't been realized in the world, so to speak. - So semantically correct, perhaps, is things that can be imagined with the human mind. No. Things that are consistent with both our imagination and our understanding of physical reality. I don't know. - Yeah, good question.
I mean, it's a good question. It's a good question. I mean, I think it is, given the way we have constructed language, it is things which fit with the things we're describing in language. It's a bit circular in the end, because, you know, you can, and the sort of boundaries of what is physically realizable.
Okay, let's take the example of motion, okay? Motion is a complicated concept. It might seem like it's a concept that should have been figured out by the Greeks, you know, long ago, but it's actually a really pretty complicated concept, 'cause what is motion? Motion is you can go from place A to place B, and it's still you when you get to the other end, right?
You take an object, you move it, and it's still the same object, but it's in a different place. Now, even in ordinary physics, that doesn't always work that way. If you're near a space-time singularity in a black hole, for example, and you take your teapot or something, you don't have much of a teapot by the time it's near the space-time singularity.
It's been completely, you know, deformed beyond recognition. But, so that's a case where pure motion doesn't really work. You can't have a thing stay the same. But, so this idea of motion is something that sort of is a slightly complicated idea, but once you have the idea of motion, you can start, once you have the idea that you're gonna describe things as being the same thing, but in a different place, that sort of abstracted idea then has, you know, that has all sorts of consequences, like this transitivity of motion, go from A to B, B to C, you've gone from A to C.
And that's, so that level of description, you can have what are sort of inevitable consequences. There are inevitable features of the way you've sort of set things up. And that's, I think, what this sort of semantic grammar is capturing, is things like that. And, you know, I think that it's a question of what does the word mean?
When you say, I go from, I move from here to there, well, it's complicated to say what that means. This is this whole issue of, you know, is pure motion possible, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. But once you have kind of got an idea of what that means, then there are inevitable consequences of that idea.
- But the very idea of meaning, it seems like there's some words that become, it's like there's a latent ambiguity to them. I mean, it's the word like emotionally loaded words, like hate and love. - Right. - It's like, what are they? What do they mean exactly? So especially when you have relationships between complicated objects, we seem to take this kind of shortcut, descriptive shortcut to describe like, object A hates object B.
What's that really mean? - Right, well, words are defined by kind of our social use of them. I mean, it's not, you know, a word, in computational language, for example, when we say we have a construct there, we expect that that construct is a building block from which we can construct an arbitrarily tall tower.
So we have to have a very solid building block. And, you know, we have to, it turns into a piece of code, it has documentation, it's a whole thing. But the word hate, you know, the documentation for that word, well, there isn't a standard documentation for that word, so to speak.
It's a complicated thing defined by kind of how we use it. When, you know, if it wasn't for the fact that we were using language, I mean, so what is language at some level? Language is a way of packaging thoughts so that we can communicate them to another mind.
- Can these complicated words be converted into something that a computation engine can use? - Right, so I think the answer to that is that what one can do in computational language is make a specific definition. And if you have a complicated word, like let's say the word eat, okay?
You'd think, oh, it's a simple word, it's, you know, animals eat things, whatever else. But, you know, you do programming, you say this function eats arguments, which is sort of poetically similar to the animal eating things. But if you start to say, well, what are the implications of, you know, the function eating something?
You know, can the function be poisoned? Well, maybe it can't actually, but, you know, if there's a type mismatch or something in some language. But, you know, in what, how far does that analogy go? And it's just an analogy. Whereas if you use the word eat in a computational language level, you would define there isn't a thing which you anchor to the kind of natural language concept eat, but it is now some precise definition of that, that then you can compute things from.
- But don't you think the analogy is also precise? Software eats the world. Don't you think there's something concrete in terms of meaning about analogies? - Sure. But the thing that sort of is the first target for computational language is to take sort of the ordinary meaning of things and try and make it precise, make it sufficiently precise, you can build these towers of computation on top of it.
So it's kind of like, if you start with a piece of poetry and you say, I'm going to define my program with this piece of poetry, it's kind of like, that's a difficult thing. It's better to say, I'm gonna just have this boring piece of prose and it's using words in the ordinary way.
And that's how I'm communicating with my computer. And that's how I'm going to build the solid building block from which I can construct this whole kind of computational tower. - So there's some sense where if you take a poem and reduce it to something computable, you're gonna have very few things left.
So maybe there's a bunch of human interaction that's just poetic, aimless nonsense. That's just like recreational hamstring a wheel. It's not actually producing anything. - Well, I think that that's a complicated thing because in a sense, human linguistic communication is there's one mind, it's producing language, that language is having an effect on another mind.
And the question of the sort of a type of effect that is well-defined, let's say, where for example, it's very independent of the two minds. It doesn't, you know, there's communication where it can matter a lot, sort of what the experience of one mind is versus another one and so on.
- Yeah, but what is the purpose of natural language communication? - Well, I think the-- - Versus, so computational language somehow feels more amenable to the definition of purpose. It's like, yeah, you're given two clean representations of a concept and you can build a tower based on that. Is natural language the same thing but more fuzzy?
- Well, I think the story of natural language, that's the great invention of our species. We don't know whether it exists in other species, but we know it exists in our species. It's the thing that allows you to sort of communicate abstractly from like one generation of the species to another.
You can, you know, there is an abstract version of knowledge that can be passed down. It doesn't have to be, you know, genetics. It doesn't have to be, you know, you don't have to apprentice the next species, you know, the next generation of birds to the previous one to show them how something works.
There is this abstracted version of knowledge that can be kind of passed down. Now that, you know, it relies on, it still tends to rely because language is fuzzy. It does tend to rely on the fact that, you know, if we look at the, you know, some ancient language that where we don't have a chain of translations from it until what we have today, we may not understand that ancient language.
And we may not understand, you know, its concepts may be different from the ones that we have today. We still have to have something of a chain, but it is something where we can realistically expect to communicate abstract ideas. And that's, you know, that's one of the big, big roles of a language.
I think, you know, in, it's, you know, that's been this ability to sort of concretify abstract things is what language has provided. - Do you see natural language and thought as the same? The stuff that's going inside your mind? - Well, that's been a long debate in philosophy. - It seems to be become more important now when we think about how intelligent GPT is.
- Whatever that means. - Whatever that means, but it seems like the stuff that's going on in the human mind seems something like intelligence. - Yeah. - And it's language. - But we call it intelligence. - Yeah, we call it, well, yes. And so you start to think of, okay, what's the relationship between thought, the language of thought, the laws of thought, the laws of, then the words like reasoning, and the laws of language, and how that has to do with computation, which seems like a more rigorous, precise ways of reasoning.
- Right, which are beyond human. I mean, much of what computers do, humans do not do. I mean, you might say-- - Humans are a subset, presumably. - Yes. - Hopefully. - Yes, yes, right. You know, you might say, who needs computation when we have large language models? Large language models can just, eventually you'll have a big enough neural net, it can do anything.
But they're really doing the kinds of things that humans quickly do. And there are plenty of sort of formal things that humans never quickly do. For example, I don't know, you know, you can, some people can do mental arithmetic, they can do a certain amount of math in their minds.
I don't think many people can run a program in their minds of any sophistication. It's just not something people do, it's not something people have even thought of doing, 'cause it's just, it's kind of not, you know, you can easily run it on a computer. - An arbitrary program.
- Yeah. - Aren't we running specialized programs? - Yeah, yeah, yeah. But if I say to you, here's a Turing machine, you know, tell me what it does after 50 steps. And you're like, trying to think about that in your mind. That's really hard to do. It's not what people do.
I mean-- - Well, in some sense, people program, they build a computer, they program it, just to answer your question about what the system does after 50 steps. I mean, humans build computers. - Yes, yes, yes, that's right. But they've created something which is then, you know, then when they run it, it's doing something different than what's happening in their minds.
I mean, they've outsourced that piece of computation from something that is internally happening in their minds to something that is now a tool that's external to their mind. - So by the way, humans, to you, didn't invent computers, they discovered them. - They discovered computation. - Which-- - They invented the technology of computers.
- The computer is just a kind of way to plug into this whole stream of computation. There's probably other ways. There's probably a lot of ways. - Well, for sure. I mean, the particular ways that we make computers out of semiconductors and electronics and so on, that's the particular technology stack we built.
I mean, the story of a lot of what people try to do with quantum computing is finding different sort of underlying physical infrastructure for doing computation. You know, biology does lots of computation. It does it using an infrastructure that's different from semiconductors and electronics. It's a molecular scale sort of computational process that hopefully we'll understand more about.
I have some ideas about understanding more about that. But that's another, it's another representation of computation. Things that happen in the physical universe at the level of these evolving hypergraphs and so on, that's another sort of implementation layer for this abstract idea of computation. - So if GPT or large language models are starting to form, starting to develop or implicitly understand the laws of language and thought, do you think they can be made explicit?
- Yes. - How? - With a bunch of effort. I mean, it's like doing natural science. I mean, what is happening in natural science? You have the world that's doing all these complicated things and then you discover, you know, Newton's laws, for example. This is how motion works. This is the way that this particular sort of idealization of the world, this is how we describe it in a simple computationally reducible way.
And I think it's the same thing here. It's there are sort of computationally reducible aspects of what's happening that you can get a kind of narrative theory for, just as we've got narrative theories in physics and so on. - Do you think it will be depressing or exciting when all the laws of thought are made explicit, human thought made explicit?
- I think that once you understand computational reducibility, it's neither of those things. Because the fact is people say, for example, people will say, "Oh, but, you know, I have free will. "I kind of, you know, I operate in a way that is, "you know, they have the idea that they're doing something "that is sort of internal to them, "that they're figuring out what's happening." But in fact, we think there are laws of physics that ultimately determine, you know, every electrical impulse in a nerve and things like this.
So you might say, "Isn't it depressing "that we are ultimately just determined "by the rules of physics, so to speak?" It's the same thing. It's at a higher level. It's like it's a shorter distance to get from kind of semantic grammar to the way that we might construct a piece of text than it is to get from individual nerve firings to how we construct a piece of text.
But it's not fundamentally different. And by the way, as soon as we have this kind of level of, you know, this other level of description, it's kind of, it helps us to go even further. So we'll end up being able to produce more and more complicated kinds of things that just like when we, you know, if we didn't have a computer and we knew certain rules, we could write them down, we'd go a certain distance.
But once we have a computer, we can go vastly further, and this is the same kind of thing. - You wrote a blog post titled, "What is Chad GPT doing and why does it work?" We've been talking about this, but can we just step back and linger on this question?
What's Chad GPT doing? What are these, a bunch of billion parameters trained on a large number of words. Why does it seem to work again? Is it because to the point you made that there's laws of language that can be discovered by such a process? Is there something more to it?
- Well, let's talk about sort of the low level of what Chad GPT is doing. I mean, ultimately you give it a prompt, it's trying to work out, you know, what should the next word be, right? - Which is wild. - Isn't that surprising to you that this kind of low level, dumb training procedure can create something syntactically correct first, and then semantically correct second?
- You know, the thing that has been sort of a story of my life, is realizing that simple rules can do much more complicated things than you imagine. That something that starts simple and starts simple to describe, can grow a thing that is, you know, vastly more complicated than you can imagine.
And honestly, it's taken me, I don't know, I've sort of been thinking about this now 40 years or so, and it always surprises me. I mean, even for example, in our physics project, sort of thinking about the whole universe growing from these simple rules, I still resist, because I keep on thinking, you know, how can something really complicated arise from something that simple?
It just seems, you know, it seems wrong, but yet, you know, the majority of my life, I've kind of known from things I've studied that this is the way things work. So yes, it is wild that it's possible to write a word at a time and produce a coherent essay, for example.
But it's worth understanding kind of how that's working. I mean, it's kind of like, if it was going to say, you know, the cat sat on the, what's the next word? Okay, so how does it figure out the next word? Well, it's seen a trillion words written on the internet, and it's seen the cat sat on the floor, the cat sat on the sofa, the cat sat on the whatever.
So it's minimal thing to do is just say, let's look at what we saw on the internet. We saw, you know, 10,000 examples of the cat sat on the, what was the most probable next word? Let's just pick that out and say that's the next word. And that's kind of what it, at some level, is trying to do.
Now, the problem is there isn't enough text on the internet to, if you have a reasonable length of prompt, that specific prompt will never have occurred on the internet. And as you kind of go further, there just won't be a place where you could have trained, you know, where you could just worked out probabilities from what was already there.
You know, like if you say two plus two, there'll be a zillion examples of two plus two equaling four and a very small number of examples of two plus two equals five and so on. And you can pretty much know what's going to happen. So then the question is, well, if you can't just work out from examples, what's going to happen, just no probabilistic, for example, what's going to happen, you have to have a model.
And there's kind of an idea, this idea of making models of things is an idea that really, I don't know, I think Galileo probably was one of the first people who sort of worked this out. I mean, it's kind of like, you know, I think I gave an example of that little book I wrote about Chachi B'tee where it's kind of like, you know, Galileo was dropping cannonballs off the different floors of the Tower of Pisa.
And it's like, okay, you drop a cannonball off this floor, you drop a cannonball off this floor, you miss floor five or something for whatever reason, but you know the time it took the cannonball to fall to the ground from floors one, two, three, four, six, seven, eight, for example, then the question is, can you work out, can you make a model which figures out how long did it take the ball, how long would it take the ball to fall to the ground from the floor you didn't explicitly measure?
And the thing Galileo realized is that you can use math, you can use mathematical formulas to make a model for how long it will take the ball to fall. So now the question is, well, okay, you want to make a model for, for example, something much more elaborate, like you've got this arrangement of pixels and is this arrangement of pixels an A or a B?
Does it correspond to something we'd recognize as an A or B? And you can make a similar kind, you know, each pixel is like a parameter in some equation and you could write down this giant equation where the answer is either, you know, A or, you know, one or two, A or B.
And the question is then what kind of a model successfully reproduces the way that we humans would conclude that this is an A and this is a B? You know, if there's a complicated extra tail on the top of the A, would we then conclude something different? What is the type of model that maps well into the way that we humans make distinctions about things?
And the big kind of meta discovery is neural nets are such a model. It's not obvious they would be such a model. It could be that human distinctions are not captured. You know, we could try searching around for a type of model that could be a mathematical model, it could be some model based on something else that captures kind of typical human distinctions about things.
It turns out this model that actually is very much the way that we think the architecture of brains works, that perhaps not surprisingly, that model actually corresponds to the way we make these distinctions. And so, you know, the core next point is that the kind of model, this neural net model, makes sort of distinctions and generalizes things in sort of the same way that we humans do it.
And that's why when you say, you know, the cat sat on the green blank, even though it never, it didn't see many examples of the cat sat on the green whatever, it can make a, or the aardvark sat on the green whatever, I'm sure that particular sentence does not occur on the internet.
And so it has to make a model that concludes what, you know, it has to kind of generalize from what it's, from the actual examples that it's seen. And so, you know, that's the fact is that neural nets generalize in the same kind of way that we humans do.
If we were, you know, the aliens might look at our neural net generalizations and say, that's crazy. You know, that thing, when you put that extra little dot on the A, that isn't an A anymore. That's, you know, that messed the whole thing up. But for us humans, we make distinctions which seem to correspond to the kinds of distinctions that neural nets make.
So then, you know, the thing that is just amazing to me about ChachiBT is how similar the structure it has is to the very original way people imagine neural nets might work back in 1943. And, you know, there's a lot of detailed engineering, you know, great cleverness, but it's really the same idea.
And in fact, even the sort of elaborations of that idea where people said, let's put in some actual particular structure to try and make the neural net more elaborate, to be very clever about it. Most of that didn't matter. I mean, there's some things that seem to, you know, when you train this neural net, you know, the one thing, this kind of transformer architecture, this attention idea, that really has to do with, does every one of these neurons connect to every other neuron, or is it somehow causally localized, so to speak?
Does it like we're making a sequence of words and the words depend on previous words, rather than just everything can depend on everything. And that seems to be important in just organizing things so that you don't have a sort of a giant mess. But the thing, you know, the thing worth understanding about what is ChachiBT in the end?
I mean, what is a neural net in the end? A neural net in the end is each neuron has a, it's taking inputs from a bunch of other neurons. It's eventually, it's going to have a numerical value. It's going to compute some number, and it's saying, I'm gonna look at the neurons above me.
It's kind of a series of layers. It's gonna look at the neurons above me, and it's going to say, what are the values of all those neurons? Then it's gonna add those up and multiply them by these weights, and then it's going to apply some function that says if it's bigger than zero or something, then make it one, or otherwise make it zero, or some slightly more complicated function.
You know very well how this works. - It's a giant equation with a lot of variables. You mentioned figuring out where the ball falls when you don't have data on the fourth floor. This, the equation here is not as simple as-- - Right, it's an equation with 175 billion terms.
- And it's quite surprising that in some sense, a simple procedure of training such an equation can lead to a good representation of natural language. - Right, the real issue is, you know, this architecture of a neural net, where what's happening is, you know, you've turned, so neural nets always just deal with numbers.
And so, you know, you've turned the sentence that you started with into a bunch of numbers. Like, let's say by mapping, you know, each word of the 50,000 words in English, you just map each word or each part of a word into some number. They feed all those numbers in, and then the thing is going to, and then those numbers just go into the values of these neurons, and then what happens is, it's just rippling down, going layer to layer, until it gets to the end.
I think "Chat GPG" has about 400 layers. And you're just, you know, it just goes once through. It just, every new word it's gonna compute, just says, here are the numbers from the words before. Let's compute the, what does it compute? It computes the probabilities that it estimates for each of the possible 50,000 words that could come next.
And then it decides, sometimes it will use the most probable word, sometimes it will use not the most probable word. It's an interesting fact that there's this so-called temperature parameter, which, you know, at temperature zero, it's always using the most probable word that it estimated was the most probable thing to come next.
You know, if you increase the temperature, it'll be more and more kind of random in its selection of words. It'll go down to lower and lower probability words. Thing I was just playing with actually recently was the transition that happens as you increase the temperature. The thing goes bonkers at a particular, you know, sometimes at a particular temperature, I think maybe about 1.2 is the thing I was noticing from yesterday, actually, that, you know, usually it's giving reasonable answers.
And then at that temperature with some probability, it just starts spouting nonsense. And, you know, nobody knows why this happens. I mean, it's, and by the way, I mean, the thing to understand is it's putting down one word at a time, but the outer loop of the fact that it says, okay, I put down a word.
Now let's take the whole thing I wrote so far. Let's feed that back in. Let's put down another word. That outer loop, which seems almost trivial, is really important to the operation of the thing. And for example, one of the things that is kind of funky is it'll give an answer.
And you say to it, is that answer correct? And it'll say, no. And why has that happened? - It's fascinating, right? - Right, why can it do that? Well, the answer is because it is going one word at a time, sort of forwards. And it didn't, you know, it came along with some sort of chain of thought in a sense, and it came up with completely the wrong answer.
But as soon as you feed it, the whole thing that it came up with, it immediately knows that that isn't right. It immediately can recognize that was a, you know, a bad syllogism or something, and can see what happened. Even though, as it was being led down this garden path, so to speak, it didn't, it came to the wrong place.
- But it's fascinating that this kind of procedure converges to something that forms a pretty good compressed representation of language on the internet. - Yeah. - That's quite-- - Right, right, right. - I'm not sure what to make of it. - Well, look, I think, you know, there are many things we don't understand, okay?
So for example, you know, 175 billion weights, it's maybe about a trillion bytes of information, which is very comparable to the training set that was used. And, you know, why that, why kind of, it sort of stands to some kind of reason that the number of weights in the neural net, I don't know, I can't really argue that.
I can't really give you a good, you know, in a sense, the very fact that, you know, insofar as there are definite rules of what's going on, you might expect that eventually we'll have a much smaller neural net that will successfully capture what's happening. I don't think the best way to do it is probably a neural net.
I think a neural net is what you do when you don't know any other way to structure the thing. And it's a very good thing to do if you don't know any other way to structure the thing. And for the last 2000 years, we haven't known any other way to structure it.
So this is a pretty good way to start. But that doesn't mean you can't find, sort of, in a sense, more symbolic rules for what's going on that, you know, much of which will then be, you can kind of get rid of much of the structure of the neural nets and replace it by things which are sort of pure steps of computation, so to speak, sort of with neural net stuff around the edges.
And that becomes just a, you know, it's just a much simpler way to do it. - So the neural net, you hope, will reveal to us good symbolic rules that make the need of the neural net less and less and less. - Right. And there will still be some stuff that's kind of fuzzy, just like, you know, there are things that, it's like this question of what can we formalize?
What can we turn into computational language? What is just sort of, oh, it happens that way just because brains are set up that way? - What do you think are the limitations of large language models, just to make it explicit? - Well, I mean, I think that deep computation is not what large language models do.
I mean, that's just, it's a different kind of thing. You know, the outer loop of a large language model, if you're trying to do many steps in a computation, the only way you get to do that right now is by spooling out, you know, all the, the whole chain of thought as a bunch of words, basically.
And, you know, you can make a Turing machine out of that, if you want to. I just was doing that construction. You know, in principle, you can make an arbitrary computation by just spooling out the words, but it's a bizarre and inefficient way to do it. But it's something where the, you know, I think that's, you know, sort of the deep computation.
It's really what humans can do quickly, large language models will probably be able to do well. Anything that you can do kind of off the top of your head type thing is really, you know, is good for large language models. And the things you do off the top of your head, you may not get them always right, but, you know, you'll, it's thinking it through the same way we do.
- But I wonder if there's an automated way to do something that humans do well, much faster to where it like loops. So generate arbitrary large code bases of Wolfram language, for example. - Well, the question is, what does he, what do you want the code base to do?
- Escape control and take over the world. - Okay. So, you know, the thing is when people say, you know, we want to build this giant thing, right? A giant piece of computational language. In a sense, it's sort of a failure of computational language if the thing you have to build, in other words, if we have a description, if you have a small description, that's the thing that you represent in computational language.
And then the computer can compute from that. - Yes. - So in a sense in, you know, when as soon as you're giving a description that, you know, if you have to somehow make that description something, you know, definite, something formal, and once, and to say, to say, okay, I'm gonna give this piece of natural language, and then it's gonna split out this giant formal structure, that in a sense that doesn't really make sense because except in so far as that piece of natural language kind of plugs into what we socially know, so to speak, plugs into kind of our corpus of knowledge, then, you know, that's a way we're capturing a piece of that corpus of knowledge, but hopefully we will have done that in computational language.
How do you make it do something that's big? Well, you know, you have to have a way to describe what you want. - Okay, I can make it more explicit if you want. How about, I just pop into my head, iterate through all the members of Congress and figure out how to convince them that they have to let me, this meaning the system, become president, pass all the laws that allows AI systems to take control and be the president, I don't know.
So that's a very explicit, like, figure out the individual life story of each congressman, each senator, anybody, I don't know, what's required to really kind of pass legislation and figure out how to control them and manipulate them, get all the information. What would be the biggest fear of this congressman and in such a way that you can take action on it in the digital space?
So maybe threaten the destruction of reputation or something like this. - Right, if I can describe what I want, you know, to what extent can a large language model automate that? - With the help of concretization of something like Wolfram Language. That makes it more, yeah, grounded. It can go rather a long way.
- I'm also surprised how quickly I was able to generate - Yeah, yeah, right. - A quick attack. - That's, yeah, you know. - I swear I did not think about this before, and it's funny how quickly, which is a very concerning thing, 'cause that probably, this idea, will probably do quite a bit of damage, and there might be a very large number of other such ideas.
- Well, I'll give you a much more benign version of that idea, okay? You're gonna make an AI tutoring system, and that's a benign version of what you're saying, is I want this person to understand this point. - Yes. - You're essentially doing machine learning where the loss function, the thing you're trying to get to, is get the human to understand this point.
And when you do a test on the human, that they, yes, they correctly understand how this or that works. And I am confident that, you know, sort of a large language model type technology combined with computational language is going to be able to do pretty well at teaching us humans things.
And it's gonna be an interesting phenomenon because, you know, sort of individualized teaching is a thing that has been kind of a goal for a long time. I think we're gonna get that, and I think more, you know, it has many consequences for, you know, like just, you know, if you know me, as in if you, the AI, know me, tell me, I'm about to do this thing, what are the three things I need to know, you know, given what I already know, you know, what's, let's say I'm looking at some paper or something, right, it's like there's a version of the summary of that paper that is optimized for me, so to speak.
And where it really is, and I think that's really going to work. - It could understand the major gaps in your knowledge that if filled would actually give you a deeper understanding of the topic here. - Right, and that's a, you know, that's an important thing because it really changes, actually, I think, you know, when you think about education and so on, it really changes kind of what's worth doing, what's not worth doing and so on.
It makes, you know, I know in my life I've learned lots of different fields, and, you know, so I, I don't know, every time I'm always thinking this is the one that's going to, I'm not gonna be able to learn, but turns out sort of there are sort of meta methods for learning these things in the end.
And, you know, I think this, this idea that it becomes easier to, you know, it becomes easier to be fed knowledge, so to speak. And it becomes, you know, if you need to know this particular thing, you can, you know, you can get taught it in an efficient way.
It's something I think is sort of an interesting feature. And I think it makes the, you know, things like the value of big towers of specialized knowledge become less significant compared to the kind of meta knowledge of sort of understanding kind of the big picture and being able to connect things together.
I think that, you know, there's been this huge trend of let's be more and more specialized because we have to, you know, we have to sort of ascend these towers of knowledge. But by the time you can get, you know, more automation of being able to get to that place on the tower without having to go through all those steps, I think it sort of changes that picture.
- Interesting, so your intuition is that in terms of the collective intelligence of the species and the individual minds that make up that collective, there'll be more, there will trend towards being generalists and being kind of philosophers. - That's what I think. I think that's where the humans are gonna be useful.
I think that a lot of these kind of, the drilling, the mechanical working out of things is much more automatable. It's much more AI territory, so to speak. - No more PhDs. - Well, that's interesting, yes. I mean, you know, the kind of the specialization, this kind of tower of specialization, which has been a feature of, you know, we've accumulated lots of knowledge in our species.
And, you know, in a sense, every time we have a kind of automation, a building of tools, it becomes less necessary to know that whole tower. And it becomes something where you can just use a tool to get to the top of that tower. I think that, you know, the thing that is ultimately, you know, when we think about, okay, what do the AIs do versus what do the humans do?
It's like AIs, you tell them, you say, go achieve this particular objective. Okay, they can maybe figure out a way to achieve that objective. We say, what objective would you like to achieve? The AI has no intrinsic idea of that. It's not a defined thing. That's a thing which has to come from some other, you know, some other entity.
And insofar as we are in charge, so to speak, or whatever it is, and our kind of web of society and history and so on is the thing that is defining what objective we want to go to, that's, you know, that's a thing that we humans are necessarily involved in, so to speak.
- To push back a little bit, don't you think that GPT, future versions of GPT would be able to give a good answer to what objective would you like to achieve? - From on what basis? I mean, if they say, look, here's the terrible thing that could happen, okay?
They're taking the average of the internet, and they're saying, you know, from the average of the internet, what do people want to do? - Well, that's the Elon Musk adage of the most entertaining outcome is the most likely. - Okay, I haven't heard that one from him, yeah. - That could be one objective, is maximize global entertainment.
The dark version of that is drama. The good version of that is fun. - Right, so I mean, this question of what, you know, if you say to the AI, what does the species want to achieve? - Yes. - Okay. - There'll be an answer, right? - There'll be an answer.
It'll be what the average of the internet says the species wants to achieve. - I think you're using the word average very loosely there, right? So I think the answers will become more and more interesting as these language models are trained better and better. - No, but I mean, in the end, it's a reflection back of what we've already said.
- Yes, but there's a deeper wisdom to the collective intelligence, presumably, than each individual. - Maybe. - Isn't that what we're trying to do as a society? - Well, I mean, that's an important, that's an interesting question. I mean, in so far as some of us work on trying to innovate and figure out new things and so on, it is sometimes, it's a complicated interplay between sort of the individual doing the crazy thing off in some spur, so to speak, versus the collective that's trying to do sort of the high inertia average thing.
And it's, you know, sometimes the collective, you know, is bubbling up things that are interesting, and sometimes it's pulling down kind of the attempt to make this kind of innovative direction. - Well, don't you think the large language models would see beyond that simplification, will say maybe intellectual and career diversity is really important.
So you need the crazy people on the outlier, on the outskirts. And so like the actual, what's the purpose of this whole thing is to explore through this kind of dynamics that we've been using as a human civilization, which is most of us focus on one thing, and then there's the crazy people on the outskirts doing the opposite of that one thing, and you kind of pull the whole society together.
There's the mainstream science, and then there's the crazy science, and it's just been the history of human civilization. And maybe the AI system will be able to see that. And the more and more impressed we are by a language model telling us this, the more control we'll give it to it, and the more we'll be willing to let it run our society.
And hence, there's this kind of loop where the society could be manipulated to let the AI system run it. - Right, well, I mean, look, one of the things that's sort of interesting is we might say we always think we're making progress, but yet, if in a sense by saying, let's take what already exists and use that as a model for what should exist, then it's interesting that, for example, many religions have taken that point of view.
There is a sacred book that got written at time X, and it defines how people should act for all future time. And it's a model that people have operated with. And in a sense, this is a version of that kind of statement. It's like, take the 2023 version of sort of how the world has exposed itself and use that to define what the world should do in the future.
- But it's an imprecise definition, right? Because just like with religious texts and with GPT, the human interpretation of what GPT says will be the perturbation in the system. It'll be the noise. It'd be full of uncertainty. It's not like Chad GPT will tell you exactly what to do.
It'll tell you a narrative of what, it's like a turn the other cheek kind of narrative, right? That's not a fully instructive narrative. - Well, until the AIs control all the systems in the world. They will be able to very precisely tell you what to do. - Well, they'll do what they, they'll just do this or that thing.
And not only that, they'll be auto suggesting to each person, do this next, do that next. So I think it's a slightly more prescriptive situation than one has typically seen. But I think this whole question of sort of what's left for the humans, so to speak, to what extent do we, you know, this idea that there is an existing kind of corpus of purpose for humans defined by what's on the internet and so on, that's an important thing.
But then the question of sort of, as we explore what we can think of as the computational universe, as we explore all these different possibilities for what we could do, all these different inventions we could make, all these different things, the question is, which ones do we choose to follow?
Those choices are the things that, in a sense, if the humans want to still have kind of human progress, that's what we get to make those choices, so to speak. In other words, there's this idea, if you say, let's take the kind of what exists today and use that as the determiner of all of what there is in the future, the thing that is sort of the opportunity for humans is there will be many possibilities thrown up.
There are many different things that could happen or be done. And insofar as we want to be in the loop, the thing that makes sense for us to be in the loop doing is picking which of those possibilities we want. - But the degree to which there's a feedback loop, the idea that we're picking something starts becoming questionable because we're influenced by the various systems.
- Absolutely. - If that becomes more and more source of our education and wisdom and knowledge. - Absolutely. Right, the AIs take over. I mean, I've thought for a long time that it's the AR auto-suggestion. That's really the thing that makes the AIs take over. It's just that the humans just follow.
- We will no longer write emails to each other. We'll just send the auto-suggested email. - Yeah, yeah. But the thing where humans are potentially in the loop is when there's a choice. And when there's a choice which we could make based on our kind of whole web of history and so on, and that's insofar as it's all just determined the humans don't have a place.
And by the way, I mean, at some level, it's all kind of a complicated philosophical issue because at some level, the universe is just doing what it does. We are parts of that universe that are necessarily doing what we do, so to speak. Yet, we feel we have sort of agency in what we're doing, and that's its own separate kind of interesting issue.
- And we also kind of feel like we're the final destination of what the universe was meant to create. But we very well could be, and likely are some kind of intermediate step, obviously. - Yeah. We're most certainly some intermediate step. The question is if there's some cooler, more complex, more interesting things that's going to be materialized.
- The computational universe is full of such things. - But in our particular pocket, specifically. If this is the best we're gonna do or not. - We can make all kinds of interesting things in the computational universe. When we look at them, we say, yeah, you know, that's a thing.
It doesn't really connect with our current way of thinking about things. It's like in mathematics. We've got certain theorems, there are about three or four million that human mathematicians have written down and published and so on. But there are an infinite number of possible mathematical theorems. We just go out into the universe of possible theorems and pick another theorem, and then people will say, well, you know, they look at it and they say, I don't know what this theorem means.
It's not connected to the things that are part of kind of the web of history that we're dealing with. You know, I think one point to make about sort of understanding AI and its relationship to us is as we have this kind of whole infrastructure of AIs doing their thing and doing their thing in a way that is perhaps not readily understandable by us humans, you know, you might say that's a very weird situation.
How come we have built this thing that behaves in a way that we can't understand that's full of computational irreducibility, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. You know, what is this? What's it gonna feel like when the world is run by AIs whose operations we can't understand? And the thing one realizes is actually we've seen this before.
That's what happens when we exist in the natural world. The natural world is full of things that operate according to definite rules. They have all kinds of, you know, computational irreducibility. We don't understand what the natural world is doing. Occasionally, you know, when you say, you know, are the AIs gonna wipe us out, for example?
Well, it's kind of like, is the machination of the AIs going to lead to this thing that eventually comes and destroys the species? Well, we can also ask the same thing about the natural world. Are the machination of the natural world going to eventually lead to this thing that's going to, you know, make the earth explode or something like this?
Those are questions, those are, and insofar as we think we understand what's happening in the natural world, that's a result of science and natural science and so on. One of the things we can expect when there's this giant infrastructure of the AIs is that's where we have to kind of invent a new kind of natural science that kind of is the natural science that explains to us how the AIs work.
I mean, it's kind of like we can, you know, we have a, I don't know, a horse or something, and we're trying to get it to, we're trying to, you know, ride the horse and go from here to there. We don't really understand how the horse works inside, but we can get certain rules and certain, you know, approaches that we take to persuade the horse to go from here to there and take us there.
And that's the same type of thing that we're kind of dealing with with the sort of incomprehensible, computationally irreducible AIs, but we can identify these kinds of, we can find these kind of pockets of reducibility that we can kind of, you know, I don't know, we're grabbing onto the mane of the horse or something to be able to ride it, or we figure out, you know, if we do this or that to ride the horse, that that's a successful way to get it to do what we're interested in doing.
- There does seem to be a difference between a horse and a large language model or something that could be called AGI connected to the internet. So let me just ask you about big philosophical question about the threats of these things. There's a lot of people like Eliezer Yudkowsky who worry about the existential risks of AI systems.
Is that something that you worry about? You know, sometimes when you're building an incredible system like Wolfram Alpha, you can kind of get lost in it. - Oh, I try and think a little bit about the implications of what one's doing. - You know, it's like the Manhattan Project kind of situation where you're like, it's some of the most incredible physics and engineering being done, but it's like, huh, where's this gonna go?
- I think some of these arguments about kind of, you know, there'll always be a smarter AI, there'll always be, you know, and eventually the AIs will get smarter than us, and then all sorts of terrible things will happen. To me, some of those arguments remind me of kind of the ontological arguments for the existence of God and things like this.
They're kind of arguments that are based on some particular model, fairly simple model often, of kind of there is always a greater this, that, and the other, you know, this is, and that's, you know, those arguments, what tends to happen in the sort of reality of how these things develop is that it's more complicated than you expect, that the kind of simple, logical argument that says, oh, eventually there'll be a super intelligence and then it will, you know, do this and that, turns out not to really be the story.
It turns out to be a more complicated story. So for example, here's an example of an issue. Is there an apex intelligence? Just like there might be an apex predator in some, you know, ecosystem. Is there gonna be an apex intelligence, the most intelligent thing that there could possibly be?
Right? I think the answer is no, and in fact, we already know this, and it's a kind of a back to the whole computational irreducibility story. There's kind of a question of, you know, even if you have sort of a Turing machine and you have a Turing machine that runs as long as possible before it halts, you say, is this the machine, is this the apex machine that does that?
There will always be a machine that can go longer. And as you go out to the infinite collection of possible Turing machines, you'll never have reached the end, so to speak. You'll never, you'll always be able to, it's kind of like the same question of whether there'll always be another invention.
Will you always be able to invent another thing? The answer is yes. There's an infinite tower of possible inventions. - That's one definition of apex. But the other is like, which I also thought you were, which I also think might be true, is there a species that's the apex intelligence right now on Earth?
So it's not trivial to say that humans are that. - Yeah, it's not trivial. I agree. It's a, you know, I think one of the things that I've long been curious about kind of other intelligences, so to speak. I mean, I, you know, I view intelligence is like computation and it's kind of a, you know, you're sort of, you have the set of rules, you deduce what happens.
I have tended to think now that there's this sort of specialization of computation that is sort of a consciousness-like thing that has to do with these, you know, computational boundedness, single thread of experience, these kinds of things that are the specialization of computation that corresponds to a somewhat human-like experience of the world.
Now the question is, so that's, you know, there may be other intelligences like, you know, the aphorism, you know, the weather has a mind of its own. It's a different kind of intelligence that can compute all kinds of things that are hard for us to compute, but it is not well aligned with us, with the way that we think about things.
It doesn't think the way we think about things. And, you know, in this idea of different intelligences, every different mind, every different human mind is a different intelligence that thinks about things in different ways. And, you know, in terms of the kind of formalism of our physics project, we talk about this idea of a ruleal space, the space of all possible sort of rule systems, and different minds are in a sense at different points in ruleal space.
Human minds, ones that have grown up with the same kind of culture and ideas and things like this, might be pretty close in ruleal space, pretty easy for them to communicate, pretty easy to translate, pretty easy to move from one place in ruleal space that corresponds to one mind to another place in ruleal space that corresponds to another sort of nearby mind.
When we deal with kind of more distant things in ruleal space, like, you know, the pet cat or something, you know, the pet cat has some aspects that are shared with us, the emotional responses of the cat are somewhat similar to ours, but the cat is further away in ruleal space than people are, and so then the question is, you know, can we identify sort of the, can we make a translation from our thought processes to the thought processes of a cat or something like this?
And, you know, what will we get when we, you know, what will happen when we get there? And I think it's the case that many, you know, many animals, I don't know, dogs, for example, you know, they have elaborate olfactory systems, they, you know, they have sort of the smell architecture of the world, so to speak, in a way that we don't.
And so, you know, if you were sort of talking to the dog and you could, you know, communicate in a language, the dog will say, well, this is a, you know, a flowing, smelling, this, that, and the other thing, concepts that we just don't have any idea about. Now, what's interesting about that is, one day we will have chemical sensors that do a really pretty good job, you know, we'll have artificial noses that work pretty well, and we might have our augmented reality systems show us kind of the same map that the dog could see and things like this, you know, similar to what happens in the dog's brain, and eventually we will have kind of expanded in ruleal space to the point where we will have those same sensory experiences that dogs have, and we will have internalized what it means to have, you know, the smell landscape or whatever.
And so then we will have kind of colonized that part of ruleal space until, you know, we haven't gone, you know, some things that, you know, animals and so on do, we sort of successfully understand, others we do not, and the question of what kind of, what is the, you know, what representation, you know, how do we convert things that animals think about to things that we can think about, that's not a trivial thing.
And, you know, I've long been curious, I had a very bizarre project at one point of trying to make an iPad game that a cat could win against its owner. - I said that it feels like there's a deep philosophical goal there though. - Yes, yes, I mean, you know, I was curious if, you know, if pets can work in Minecraft or something and can construct things, what will they construct?
And will what they construct be something where we look at it and we say, oh yeah, I recognize that. Or will it be something that looks to us like something that's out there in the computational universe that one of my, you know, cellular automata might have produced, where we say, oh yeah, I can kind of see it operates according to some rules, I don't know why you would use those rules, I don't know why you would care.
- Yeah, actually, just to link on that seriously, is there a connector in the ruleal space between you and a cat where the cat could legitimately win? So iPad is a very limited interface. - Yeah, I-- - I wonder if there's a game where cats win. - I think the problem is that cats don't tend to be that interested in what's happening on the iPad.
- So yeah, that's an interface issue probably. - Yeah, right, right, right. No, I think it is likely that, I mean, you know, there are plenty of animals that would successfully eat us if we were, you know, if we were exposed to them. And so there's, you know, it's gonna pounce faster than we can get out of the way and so on.
So there are plenty of, and probably it's going to, you know, we think we've hidden ourselves, but we haven't successfully hidden ourselves. - That's a physical strength. I wonder if there's something more in the realm of intelligence where an animal like a cat could out-- - Well, I think there are things, certainly in terms of the speed of processing certain kinds of things, for sure.
I mean, the question of what, you know, is there a game of chess, for example, is there cat chess? That the cats could play against each other. And if we tried to play a cat, we'd always lose. I don't know. - It might have to do with speed, but it might have to do with concepts also.
There might be concepts in the cat's head. - I tend to think that our species, from its invention of language, has managed to build up this kind of tower of abstraction that for things like a chess-like game will make us win. In other words, we've become, through the fact that we've kind of experienced language and learnt abstraction, we've sort of become smarter at those kinds of abstract kinds of things.
Now, that doesn't make us smarter at catching a mouse or something. It makes us smarter at the things that we've chosen to sort of concern ourselves, which are these kinds of abstract things. And I think this is, again, back to the question of what does one care about? You know, if one's, you know, the cat, if you have the discussion with a cat, if we can translate things to have the discussion with a cat, the cat will say, you know, "I'm very excited that this light is moving," and will say, "Why do you care?" And the cat will say, "That's the most important thing "in the world, that this thing moves around." I mean, it's like when you ask about, I don't know, you look at archeological remains and you say, "These people had this belief system about this, "and that was the most important thing in the world to them." And now we look at it and say, "We don't know what the point of it was." I mean, I've been curious, you know, there are these handprints on caves from 20,000 or more years ago, and it's like, nobody knows what these handprints were there for, you know?
That they may have been a representation of the most important thing you can imagine. They may just have been some, you know, some kid who rubbed their hands in the mud and stuck them on the walls of the cave. You know, we don't know. And I think, but this whole question of what, you know, is when you say this question of sort of, "What's the smartest thing around?" There's the question of what kind of computation you're trying to do.
If you're saying, you know, if you say, "You've got some well-defined computation, "and how do you implement it?" Well, you could implement it by nerve cells, you know, firing, you can implement it with silicon and electronics. You can implement it by some kind of molecular computation process in the human immune system or in some molecular biology kind of thing.
There are different ways to implement it. And, you know, I think this question of sort of which, you know, those different implementation methods will be at different speeds, they'll be able to do different things. If you say, you know, which, so an interesting question would be, what kinds of abstractions are most natural in these different kinds of systems?
So for a cat, it's, for example, you know, the visual scene that we see, you might, you know, we pick out certain objects, we recognize, you know, certain things in that visual scene, a cat might in principle recognize different things. I suspect, you know, evolution, biological evolution is very slow.
And I suspect what a cat notices is very similar. And we even know that from some neurophysiology. What a cat notices is very similar to what we notice, of course, there's a, you know, one obvious difference is cats have only two kinds of color receptors. So they don't see in the same kind of color that we do.
Now, you know, we say we're better, we have three color receptors, you know, red, green, blue. We're not the overall winner. I think the mantis shrimp is the overall winner with 15 color receptors, I think. So it can kind of make distinctions that with our current, you know, like the mantis shrimps view of reality is, at least in terms of color is much richer than ours.
Now, but what's interesting is how do we get there? So imagine we have this augmented reality system that is even, you know, it's seeing into the infrared, into the ultraviolet, things like this. And it's translating that into something that is connectable to our brains, either through our eyes or more directly into our brains, you know, then eventually our kind of web of the types of things we understand will extend to those kinds of constructs, just as they have extended.
I mean, there are plenty of things where we see them in the modern world 'cause we made them with technology and now we understand what that is. But if we'd never seen that kind of thing, we wouldn't have a way to describe it, we wouldn't have a way to understand it and so on.
- All right, so that actually stemmed from our conversation about whether AI's gonna kill all of us. And you, we've discussed this kind of spreading of intelligence through really all space, that in practice it just seems that things get more complicated. Things are more complicated than the story of, well, if you build the thing that's plus one intelligence, that thing will be able to build the thing that's plus two intelligence and plus three intelligence and that will be exponential, it'll become more intelligent exponentially faster and so on until it completely destroys everything.
But that intuition might still not be so simple, but it might still carry validity. And there's two interesting trajectories here. One, a superintelligent system remains in really proximity to humans, to where we're like, holy crap, this thing is really intelligent. Let's elect the president. And then there could be perhaps more terrifying intelligence that starts moving away.
They might be around us now. They're moving far away in really all space, but they're still sharing physical resources with us, right? - Yes, yes. - And so they can rob us of those physical resources and destroy humans just kind of casually. - Yeah. - Just-- - Like nature could.
- Like nature could. But it seems like there's something unique about AI systems where there is this kind of exponential growth, like the way, well, sorry, nature has so many things in it. One of the things that nature has, which is very interesting, are viruses, for example. There is systems within nature that have this kind of exponential effect.
And that terrifies us humans 'cause again, there's only eight billion of us and you can just kind of, it's not that hard to just kind of whack 'em all real quick. So I mean, is that something you think about? - Yeah, I've thought about that, yes. - The threat of it.
I mean, are you as concerned about it as somebody like Eliezer Yarkovsky, for example? Just big, big, painful negative effects of AI on society. - You know, no, but perhaps that's 'cause I'm intrinsically an optimist. I mean, I think that there are things, I think the thing that one sees is there's going to be this one thing and it's going to just zap everything.
Somehow, maybe I have faith in computational irreducibility, so to speak, that there's always unintended little corners that it's just like somebody says, I'm going to, oh, I don't know, somebody has some bioweapon and they say, we're gonna release this and it's going to do all this harm. But then it turns out it's more complicated than that because some humans are different and the exact way it works is a little different than you expect.
It's something where sort of the great big, you smash the thing with something, the asteroid collides with the earth and it kind of, and yes, the earth is cold for two years or something and then lots of things die, but not everything dies. And there's usually, I mean, I kind of, this is in a sense the sort of story of computational irreducibility.
There are always unexpected corners, there are always unexpected consequences. And I don't think that they kind of whack it over the head with something and then it's all gone. Is, you know, that can obviously happen. The earth can be swallowed up in a black hole or something and then it's kind of presumably all over.
But I think this question of what, what do I think the realistic paths are? I think that there will be sort of an increasing, I mean, people have to get used to phenomena like computational irreducibility. There's an idea that we built the machines so we can understand what they do and we're going to be able to control what happens.
Well, that's not really right. Now the question is, is the result of that lack of control going to be that the machines kind of conspire and sort of wipe us out? Maybe just because I'm an optimist, I don't tend to think that that's in the cards. I think that the, you know, as a realistic thing, I suspect, you know, what will sort of emerge maybe is kind of an ecosystem of the AIs, just as, you know, again, I don't really know.
I mean, this is something it's hard to, it's hard to be clear about what will happen. I mean, I think that there are a lot of sort of details of, you know, what could we do? What systems in the world could we connect an AI to? You know, I have to say, I was just a couple of days ago, I was working on this ChatGPT plugin kit that we have for Wolfram Language, okay?
Where you can, you know, you can create a plugin and it runs Wolfram Language code and it can run Wolfram Language code back on your own computer. And I was thinking, well, I can just make it, you know, I can tell ChatGPT, create a piece of code and then just run it on my computer.
And I'm like, you know, that sort of personalizes for me the what could possibly go wrong, so to speak. - Was that exciting or scary, that possibility? - It was a little bit scary, actually, because it's kind of like, like I realize I'm delegating to the AI, just write a piece of code.
You know, you're in charge, write a piece of code, run it on my computer. And pretty soon all my files can be deleted. - That's like Russian roulette, but like much more complicated version of that. - Yes, yes, right. That's a good drinking game, I don't know. (laughing) - Well, right, I mean, that's why-- - It depends how much you're drinking.
- It's an interesting question then, if you do that, right? What is the sandboxing that you should have? And that's sort of a, that's a version of that question for the world. That is, as soon as you put the AIs in charge of things, you know, how much, how many constraints should there be on these systems before you put the AIs in charge of all the weapons and all these, you know, all these different kinds of systems?
- Well, here's the fun part about sandboxes, is the AI knows about them. It has the tools to crack them. - Look, the fundamental problem of computer security is computational irreducibility. - Yes. - Because the fact is, any sandbox is never, any, you know, it's never gonna be a perfect sandbox.
If you want the system to be able to do interesting things, I mean, this is the problem that's happened, the generic problem of computer security, that as soon as you have your, you know, firewall that is sophisticated enough to be a universal computer, that means it can do anything.
And so long as, if you find a way to poke it so that you actually get it to do that universal computation thing, that's the way you kind of crawl around and get it to do the thing that it wasn't intended to do. And that's sort of another version of computational irreducibility, is you can, you know, you can kind of, you get it to do the thing you didn't expect it to do, so to speak.
- There's so many interesting possibilities here that manifest themselves from the computational irreducibility here. It's just so many things can happen, because in digital space, things move so quickly. You can have a chatbot, you can have a piece of code that you could basically have chat GPT generate viruses, accidentally or on purpose, and they, digital viruses.
- Yes. - And they could be brain viruses too. They convince, kind of like phishing emails. - Yes. - They can convince you of stuff. - Yes, and no doubt you can, you know, in a sense we've had the loop of the machine learning loop of making things that convince people of things is surely going to get easier to do.
- Yeah. - And, you know, then what does that look like? Well, it's again, you know, we humans are, you know, we're, this is a new environment for us. And admittedly, it's an environment which a little bit scarily is changing much more rapidly than, I mean, you know, people worry about, you know, climate change is going to happen over hundreds of years.
And, you know, the environment is changing, but the environment for, you know, in the kind of digital environment might change in six months. - So one of the relevant concerns here in terms of the impact of GPT on society is the nature of truth that's relevant to Wolfram Alpha.
Because computation through symbolic reasoning that's embodied in Wolfram Alpha as the interface, there's a kind of sense that what Wolfram Alpha tells me is true. - So we hope. - Yeah, I mean, you could probably analyze that, you could show, you can't prove that's always going to be true, computation or usability, but it's going to be more true than not.
- It's, look, the fact is it will be the correct consequence of the rules you've specified. And insofar as it talks about the real world, you know, that is our job in sort of curating and collecting data to make sure that that data is "as true as possible." Now, what does that mean?
Well, you know, it's always an interesting question. I mean, for us, our operational definition of truth is, you know, somebody says, "Who's the best actress?" Who knows? But somebody won the Oscar, and that's a definite fact. And so, you know, that's the kind of thing that we can make computational as a piece of truth.
If you ask, you know, these things which, you know, a sensor measured this thing, it did it this way, a machine learning system, this particular machine learning system recognized this thing, that's a sort of a definite fact, so to speak. And that's, you know, there is a good network of those things in the world.
It's certainly the case that, particularly when you say, is so-and-so a good person? - Yeah. - You know, that's a hopelessly, you know, we might have a computational language definition of good. I don't think it'd be very interesting, 'cause that's a very messy kind of concept, not really amenable to kind of, you know, I think as far as we will get with those kinds of things is I want X.
There's a kind of meaningful calculus of I want X, and that has various consequences. I mean, I'm not sure I haven't thought this through properly but I think, you know, a concept like is so-and-so a good person, is that true or not? That's a mess. - That's a mess that's amenable to computation.
I think it's a mess when humans try to define what's good, like through legislation, but when humans try to define what's good through literature, through history books, through poetry, it starts being-- - Well, I don't know, I mean, that particular thing, it's kind of like, you know, we're going into kind of the ethics of what counts as good, so to speak, and, you know, what do we think is right, and so on.
And I think that's a thing which, you know, one feature is we don't all agree about that. There's no theorems about kind of, you know, there's no theoretical framework that says this is the way that ethics has to be. - Well, first of all, there's stuff we kind of agree on, and there's some empirical backing for what works and what doesn't from just even the morals and ethics within religious texts.
So we seem to mostly agree that murder is bad. There's certain universals that seem to emerge. - I wonder whether murder of an AI is bad. - Well, I tend to think yes, but I think we're gonna have to contend with that question. Oh, and I wonder what AI would say.
- Yeah, well, I think, you know, one of the things with AIs is it's one thing to wipe out that AI that is only, you know, it has no owner. You can easily imagine an AI kind of hanging out on the, you know, on the internet without having any particular owner or anything like that.
And then you say, well, what harm does it, you know, it's okay to get rid of that AI. Of course, if the AI has 10,000 friends who are humans, and all those, you know, all those 10,000 humans will be incredibly upset that this AI just got exterminated. It becomes a slightly different, more entangled story.
But yeah, no, I think that this question about what do humans agree about, it's, you know, there are certain things that, you know, human laws have tended to consistently agree about. You know, there've been times in history when people have sort of gone away from certain kinds of laws, even ones that we would now say, how could you possibly have not done it that way?
You know, that just doesn't seem right at all. But I think, I mean, this question of what, I don't think one can say beyond saying, if you have a set of rules that will cause the species to go extinct, that's probably, you know, you could say that's probably not a winning set of laws, because even to have a thing on which you can operate laws requires that the species not be extinct.
- But between sort of what's the distance between Chicago and New York that Wolfram Alpha can answer, and the question of if this person is good or not, there seems to be a lot of gray area. And that starts becoming really interesting. I think your, since the creation of Wolfram Alpha have been a kind of arbiter of truth at a large scale.
So the system is, generates more truth than-- - Try to make sure that the things are true. I mean, look, as a practical matter, when people write computational contracts, and it's kind of like, you know, if this happens in the world, then do this. And this hasn't developed as quickly as it might have done.
You know, this has been a sort of a blockchain story in part and so on, although blockchain is not really necessary for the idea of computational contracts. But you can imagine that eventually sort of a large part of what's in the world are these giant chains and networks of computational contracts.
And then something happens in the world, and this whole giant domino effect of contracts firing autonomously that cause other things to happen. And, you know, for us, you know, we've been the main sort of source, the Oracle of quotes, facts or truth or something for things like blockchain, computational contracts and such like.
And there's a question of, you know, what, you know, I consider that responsibility to actually get the stuff right. And one of the things that is tricky sometimes is when is it true? When is it a fact? When is it not a fact? I think the best we can do is to say, you know, we have a procedure, we follow the procedure, we might get it wrong, but at least we won't be corrupt about getting it wrong, so to speak.
- So that's beautifully put. I have a transparency about the procedure. The problem starts to emerge when the things that you convert into computational language start to expand. For example, into the realm of politics. So this is where it's almost like this nice dance of Wolfram Alpha and Chad G.B.T.
Chad G.B.T., like you said, is shallow and broad. So it's gonna give you an opinion on everything. - But it writes fiction as well as fact, which is exactly how it's built. I mean, that's exactly, it is making language and it is making both, even in code, it writes fiction.
I mean, it's kind of fun to see sometimes, you know, it'll write fictional Wolfram language code. - Yeah. - That- - It kind of looks right. - Yeah, it looks right, but it's actually not pragmatically correct. - Yeah. - But yes, it has a view of kind of roughly how the world works at the same level as books of fiction talk about roughly how the world works.
They just don't happen to be the way the world actually worked or whatever. But yes, that's, no, I agree. That's sort of a, you know, we are attempting with our whole, you know, Wolfram language, computational language thing to represent at least, well, it's either, it doesn't necessarily have to be how the actual world works 'cause we can invent a set of rules that aren't the way the actual world works and run those rules, but then we're saying we're going to accurately represent the results of running those rules, which might or might not be the actual rules of the world.
But we also are trying to capture features of the world as accurately as possible to represent what happens in the world. Now, again, as we've discussed, you know, the atoms in the world arrange, you know, you say, I don't know, you know, was there a tank that showed up, you know, that, you know, drove somewhere?
Okay, well, you know, what is a tank? It's an arrangement of atoms that we abstractly describe as a tank, and you could say, well, you know, there's some arrangement of atoms that is a different arrangement of atoms, but it's, and it's not, you know, we didn't decide, it's like this observer theory question of, you know, what arrangement of atoms counts as a tank versus not a tank?
- So there's even things that we consider strong facts. You could start to kind of disassemble them and show that they're not. - Absolutely. Right, I mean, so the question of whether, oh, I don't know, was this gust of wind strong enough to blow over this particular thing? Well, a gust of wind is a complicated concept.
You know, it's full of little pieces of fluid dynamics and little vortices here and there, and you have to define, you know, was it, you know, the aspect of the gust of wind that you care about might be it put this amount of pressure on this, you know, blade of some, you know, wind turbine or something, and, you know, that's the, but, you know, if you say, if you have something which is the fact of the gust of wind was this strong or whatever, that, you know, that is, you have to have some definition of that.
You have to have some measuring device that says according to my measuring device that was constructed this way, the gust of wind was this. - So what can you say about the nature of truth that's useful for us to understand, Chad GPT, because you've been contending with this idea of what is fact and not, and it seems like Chad GPT is used a lot now.
I've seen it used by journalists to write articles. And so you have people that are working with large language models trying to desperately figure out how do we essentially censor them through different mechanisms, either manually or through reinforcement learning with human feedback, try to align them to not say fiction, just to say nonfiction as much as possible.
- This is the importance of computational language as an intermediate. It's kind of like, you've got the large language model. It's able to surface something which is a formal precise thing that you can then look at and you can run tests on it and you can do all kinds of things.
It's always going to work the same way and it's precisely defined what it does. And then the large language model is the interface. I mean, the way I view these large language models, one of their important, I mean, there are many use cases and it's a remarkable thing. Could talk about some of these, literally every day we're coming up with a couple of new use cases, some of which are very, very, very surprising.
And things where, I mean, but the best use cases are ones where it's, even if it gets it roughly right, it's still a huge win. Like a use case we had from a week or two ago is read our bug reports. We've got hundreds of thousands of bug reports that have been accumulated over decades.
And it's like, can we have it just read the bug report, figure out where is the bug likely to be and home in on that piece of code. Maybe it'll even suggest some sort of way to fix the code. It might get that, it might be nonsense what it says about how to fix the code, but it's incredibly useful that it was able to- - It's so awesome.
It's so awesome because even the nonsense will somehow be instructive. I don't quite understand that yet. Yeah, there's so many programming related things, like for example, translating from one programming language to another is really, really interesting. It's extremely effective, but then you, the failures reveal the path forward also.
- Yeah, but I think, I mean, the big thing, I mean, in that kind of discussion, the unique thing about our computational language is it was intended to be read by humans. - Yes, that's really important. - Right, and so it has this thing where you can, but thinking about sort of chat GPT and its use and so on, one of the big things about it, I think, is it's a linguistic user interface.
That is, so a typical use case might be, take the journalist case, for example. It's like, let's say I have five facts that I'm trying to turn into an article, or I'm trying to write a report where I have basically five facts that I'm trying to include in this report.
But then I feed those five facts to chat GPT, it puffs them out into this big report. And then that's a good interface for, and if I just gave, if I just had in my terms, those five bullet points, and I gave them to some other person, the person would say, "I don't know what you're talking about, "because these are, you know, "this is your version of this sort of quick notes "about these five bullet points." But if you puff it out into this thing, which is kind of connects to the collective understanding of language, then somebody else can look at it and say, "Okay, I understand what you're talking about." Now you can also have a situation where that thing that was puffed out is fed to another large language model.
You know, it's kind of like, you know, you're applying for the permit to, you know, I don't know, grow fish in some place or something like this. And it, you know, it, and you have these facts that you're putting in, you know, I'm gonna have a, you know, I'm gonna have this kind of water and I don't know what it is.
You just got a few bullet points. It puffs it out into this big application. You fill it out. Then at the other end, you know, the fisheries bureau has another large language model that just crushes it down because the fisheries bureau cares about these three points and it knows what it cares about.
And it then, so it's really the natural language produced by the large language model is sort of a transport layer that, you know, is really LLM communicates with LLM. I mean, it's kind of like the, you know, I write a piece of email using my LLM and, you know, puff it out from the things I want to say.
Your LLM turns it into, and the conclusion is X. Now the issue is, you know, that the thing is going to make this thing that is sort of semantically plausible. And it might not actually be what you, you know, it might not be kind of relate to the world in the way that you think it should relate to the world.
Now I've seen this, you know, I've been doing, okay, I'll give you a couple of examples. I was doing this thing when we announced this plugin for chat GPT. I had this lovely example of a math word problem, some complicated thing, and it did a spectacular job of taking apart this elaborate thing about, you know, this person has twice as many chickens as this, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.
And it turned it into a bunch of equations. It fed them to Wolfram Language. We solved the equations, everybody did great. We gave back the results. And I thought, okay, I'm going to put this in this blog post I'm writing. Okay, I thought I better just check. And turns out it got everything, all the hard stuff it got right.
At the very end, last two lines, it just completely goofed it up and gave the wrong answer. And I would not have noticed this. Same thing happened to me two days ago. Okay, so I thought, you know, I made this with this chat GPT plugin kit. I made a thing that would emit a sound, would play a tune on my local computer, right?
So chat GPT would produce, you know, a series of notes and it would play this tune on my computer. Very cool. Okay, so I thought I'm going to ask it, play the tune that Hal sang when Hal was being disconnected in 2001. Okay, so there it is. - Daisy, was it Daisy?
- Yes. - Daisy, yeah. - Right, so, okay, so I think, you know, and so it produces a bunch of notes. And I'm like, this is spectacular. This is amazing. And then I thought, you know, I was just going to put it in. And then I thought I better actually play this.
And so I did, and it was "Mary Had a Little Lamb." - Oh, wow. Oh, wow. But it was "Mary Had a Little Lamb." - Yeah, yes. - Wow, so it was correct, but wrong. - Yes. - It was, you could easily be mistaken. - Yes, right. And in fact, I kind of gave the, I had this quote from Hal to explain, you know, it's as the Hal states in the movie, you know, it's the Hal 9000 is, you know, the thing was just a rhetorical device 'cause I'm realizing, oh my gosh, you know, this Chachi P'tee, you know, could have easily fooled me.
I mean, it did this, it did all the, it did this amazing thing of knowing this thing about the movie and being able to turn that into the notes of the song, except it's the wrong song. - Yeah. - And, you know, Hal, in the movie, Hal says, you know, I think it's something like, you know, no Hal 9000 series computer has ever been found to make an error.
We are for all practical purposes, perfect and incapable of error. And I thought that was kind of a charming sort of quote from Hal to make in connection with what Chachi P'tee had done in that case. - The interesting thing is about the LLMs, like you said, that they are very willing to admit their error - Well, yes.
I mean, that's a question of the RLH, the reinforcement learning human feedback thing. - Oh, right. - That's, you know, an LLM. The really remarkable thing about Chachi P'tee is, you know, I had been following what was happening with large language models and I played with them a whole bunch and they were kind of like, eh, you know, kind of like what you would expect based on sort of, sort of statistical continuation of language.
It's interesting, but it's not breakout exciting. And then I think the kind of reinforcement, the human feedback reinforcement learning, you know, in making Chachi P'tee try and do the things that humans really wanted to do, that broke through, that kind of reached this threshold where the thing really is interesting to us humans.
And by the way, it's interesting to see how, you know, you change the temperature or something like that, the thing goes bonkers and it no longer is interesting to humans. It's producing garbage. And it's kind of right, it's somehow it managed to get this above this threshold where it really is well aligned to what we humans are interested in.
And kind of that's, and I think, you know, nobody saw that coming, I think. Certainly nobody I've talked to and nobody who was involved in that project seems to have known that was coming. It's just one of these things that is a sort of remarkable threshold. I mean, you know, when we built Wolfram Alpha, for example, I didn't know it was gonna work.
You know, we tried to build something that would have enough knowledge of the world, that it could answer a reasonable set of questions, that we could do good enough natural language understanding that typical things you type in would work. We didn't know where that threshold was. I mean, I was not sure that it was the right decade to try and build this, even the right, you know, 50 years to try and build it.
You know, and I think that was, it's the same type of thing with "Chat GPT" that I don't think anybody could have predicted that, you know, 2022 would be the year that this became possible. - I think, yeah, you tell a story about Marvin Minsky and showing it to him and saying, like, no, no, no, this time it actually works.
- Yes, yes, and I mean, you know, it's the same thing for me looking at these large language models. It's like when people are first saying in the first few weeks of "Chat GPT," it's like, oh yeah, you know, I've seen these large language models. And then, you know, and then I actually try it and, you know, oh my gosh, it actually works.
And I think it's, but, you know, the things, and the thing I found, you know, I remember one of the first things I tried was write a persuasive essay that a wolf is the bluest kind of animal, okay? So it writes this thing and it starts talking about these wolves that live on the Tibetan plateau and they're named some Latin name and so on.
And I'm like, really? And I'm starting to look it up on the web and it's like, well, it's actually complete nonsense. But it's extremely plausible. I mean, it's plausible enough that I was going and looking it up on the web and wondering if there was a wolf that was blue.
You know, I mentioned this on some live streams I've done and so people have been sending me these pictures. - Blue wolves? - Blue wolves. - Maybe it was onto something. - Can you kind of give your wise sage advice about what humans who have never interacted with AI systems, not even like with Wolfram Alpha, are now interacting with Chad GPT, because it becomes, it's accessible to a certain demographic that may have not touched AI systems before.
What do we do with truth? Like journalists, for example. How do we think about the output of these systems? - I think this idea, the idea that you're going to get factual output is not a very good idea. I mean, it's just, this is not, it is a linguistic interface.
It is producing language and language can be truthful or not truthful. And that's a different slice of what's going on. I think that, you know, what we see in, for example, kind of, you know, go check this with your fact source, for example. You can do that to some extent, but then it's going to not check something.
It's going, you know, that is again, a thing that is sort of a, does it check in the right place? I mean, we see that in, you know, does it call the, you know, the Wolfram plugin in the right place? You know, often it does, sometimes it doesn't. You know, I think the real thing to understand about what's happening is, which I think is very exciting, is kind of the great democratization of access to computation.
- Yeah. - And, you know, I think that when you look at sort of the, there's been a long period of time when computation and the ability to figure out things with computers has been something that kind of only the druids at some level can achieve. You know, I myself have been involved in trying to sort of de-druidify access to computation.
I mean, back before Mathematica existed, you know, in 1988, if you were a physicist or something like that, and you wanted to do a computation, you would find a programmer, you would go and, you know, delegate the computation to that programmer. Hopefully they'd come back with something useful. Maybe they wouldn't.
There'd be this long, you know, multi-week, you know, loop that you go through. And then it was actually very, very interesting to see, 1988, you know, like first people like physicists, mathematicians, and so on, then other, lots of other people, but this very rapid transition of people realizing they themselves could actually type with their own fingers and, you know, make some piece of code that would do a computation that they cared about.
And, you know, it's been exciting to see lots of discoveries and so on made by using that tool. And I think the same thing is, you know, and we see the same thing, you know, Wolfram Alpha is dealing with, it is not as deep computation as you can achieve with whole Wolfram Language Mathematica stack.
But the thing that's, to me, particularly exciting about kind of the large language model, linguistic interface mechanism, is it dramatically broadens the access to kind of deep computation. I mean, it's kind of like, one of the things I've sort of thought about recently is, you know, what's gonna happen to all these programmers?
What's gonna happen to all these people who, you know, a lot of what they do is write slabs of boilerplate code. And in a sense, you know, I've been saying for 40 years, that's not a very good idea. You know, you can automate a lot of that stuff with a high enough level language, that slab of code that's designed in the right way, you know, that slab of code turns into this one function we just implemented that you can just use.
So in a sense, the fact that there's all of this activity of doing sort of lower level programming is something, for me, it seemed like, I don't think this is the right thing to do. But, you know, and lots of people have used our technology and not had to do that.
But the fact is that that's, you know, so when you look at, I don't know, computer science departments that have turned into places where people are learning the trade of programming, so to speak, it's sort of a question of what's gonna happen. And I think there are two dynamics.
One is that kind of sort of boilerplate programming is going to become, you know, it's going to go the way that assembly language went back in the day of something where it's really mostly specified by at a higher level, you know, you start with natural language, you turn it into a computational language, that's you look at the computational language, you run tests, you understand that's what's supposed to happen.
You know, if we do a great job with compilation of the, you know, of the computational language, it might turn into LLVM or something like this, but, you know, or it just directly gets run through the algorithms we have and so on. But then, so that's kind of a tearing down of this kind of this big structure that's been built of teaching people programming.
But on the other hand, the other dynamic is vastly more people are gonna care about computation. So all those departments of, you know, art history or something that really didn't use computation before now have the possibility of accessing it by virtue of this kind of linguistic interface mechanism. - And if you create an interface that allows you to interpret the debug and interact with the computational language, then that makes it even more accessible.
- Yeah, well, I mean, I think the thing is that right now, you know, the average, you know, art history student or something probably isn't going to, you know, they're not probably, they don't think they know about programming and things like this. But by the time it really becomes a kind of purely, you know, you just walk up to it, there's no documentation, you start just typing, you know, compare these pictures with these pictures and, you know, see the use of this color, whatever.
And you generate this piece of computational language code that gets run, you see the result, you say, oh, that looks roughly right, or you say, that's crazy. And maybe then you eventually get to say, well, I better actually try and understand what this computational language code did. And that becomes the thing that you learn, just like, it's kind of an interesting thing because unlike with mathematics, where you kind of have to learn it before you can use it, this is a case where you can use it before you have to learn it.
- Well, I got a sad possibility here, or maybe exciting possibility, that very quickly people won't even look at the computational language. They'll trust that it's generated correctly as you get better and better at generating that language. - Yes, I think that there will be enough cases where people see, you know, 'cause you can make it generate tests too.
- Yes. - And so you'll say, we're doing that. I mean, it's a pretty cool thing actually. - Yes. - You know, say this is the code, and you know, here are a bunch of examples of running the code. - Yeah. - Okay, people will at least look at those, and they'll say that example is wrong, and you know, then it'll kind of wind back from there.
And I agree that the kind of the intermediate level of people reading the computational language code, in some case, people will do that, in other case, people just look at the tests, and or even just look at the results. And sometimes it'll be obvious that you got the thing you wanted to get, because you were just describing, you know, make me this interface that has two sliders here, and you can see it has those two sliders there, and that's kind of, that's the result you want.
But I think, you know, one of the questions then is, in that setting where, you know, you have this kind of ability, broad ability of people to access computation, what should people learn? You know, in other words, right now, you know, you go to computer science school, so to speak, and a large part of what people end up learning, I mean, it's been a funny historical development, because back, you know, 30, 40 years ago, computer science departments were quite small, and they taught, you know, things like finite automata theory and compiler theory and things like this.
You know, a company like mine rarely hired people who'd come out of those programs, 'cause the stuff they knew was, I think it's very interesting, I love that theoretical stuff, but, you know, it wasn't that useful for the things we actually had to build in software engineering. And then kind of there was this big pivot in the '90s, I guess, where there was a big demand for sort of IT-type programming and so on and software engineering, and then, you know, big demand from students and so on, you know, we want to learn this stuff.
And I think, you know, the thing that really was happening in part was lots of different fields of human endeavor were becoming computational. You know, for all X, there was a computational X. And this is a, and that was a thing that the people were responding to. But then kind of this idea emerged that to get to that point, the main thing you had to do was to learn this kind of trade or skill of doing, you know, programming language-type programming.
And that, you know, it kind of, it's a strange thing, actually, because I, you know, I remember back when I used to be in the professoring business, which is now 35 years ago, so, gosh, that's rather a long time ago. - Time flies. - You know, it was right when there were just starting to emerge kind of computer science departments at sort of fancy research universities and so on.
I mean, some had already had it, but the other ones that were just starting to have that. And it was kind of a thing where they were kind of wondering, are we going to put this thing that is essentially a trade-like skill, are we going to somehow attach this to the rest of what we're doing?
And a lot of these kind of knowledge work-type activities have always seemed like things where that's where the humans have to go to school and learn all this stuff, and that's never going to be automated. And, you know, this is, it's kind of shocking that rather quickly, you know, a lot of that stuff is clearly automatable.
And I think, you know, but the question then is, okay, so if it isn't worth learning kind of, you know, how to do car mechanics, you only need to know how to drive the car, so to speak, what do you need to learn? And, you know, in other words, if you don't need to know the mechanics of how to tell the computer in detail, you know, make this loop, you know, set this variable, you know, set up this array, whatever else, if you don't have to learn that stuff, you don't have to learn the kind of under the hood things, what do you have to learn?
I think the answer is you need to have an idea where you want to drive the car. In other words, you need to have some notion of, you know, you need to have some picture of sort of what the architecture of what is computationally possible is. - Well, there's also this kind of artistic element of conversation because you ultimately, you use natural language to control the car.
So it's not just where you want to go. - Well, yeah, you know, it's interesting. It's a question of who's going to be a great prompt engineer. - Yeah. - Okay. So my current theory this week, good expository writers are good prompt engineers. - What's an expository writer? So like a- - Somebody who can explain stuff well.
- Huh, but which department does that come from? - In the university? - Yeah. - I have no idea. I think they killed off all the expository writing departments. - Well, there you go, strong words with Stephen Wolfram. - Well, I don't know. I'm not sure if that's right.
I mean, I actually am curious, 'cause in fact, I just sort of initiated this kind of study of what's happened to different fields at universities. 'Cause like, you know, there used to be geography departments at all universities, and then they disappeared. Actually, right before GIS became common, I think they disappeared.
You know, linguistics departments came and went in many universities. And it's kind of interesting because these things that people have thought were worth learning at one time, and then they kind of die off. And then, you know, I do think that it's kind of interesting that for me writing prompts, for example, I realize, you know, I think I'm an okay expository writer.
And I realize when I'm sloppy writing a prompt and I don't really think, 'cause I'm thinking I'm just talking to an AI. I don't need to, you know, try and be clear in explaining things. That's when it gets totally confused. - And I mean, in some sense, you have been writing prompts for a long time with Wolfram Alpha, thinking about this kind of stuff.
- Yeah. - How do you convert natural language into computation? - Well, right. But that's, you know, the one thing that I'm wondering about is, you know, it is remarkable the extent to which you can address an LLM like you can address a human, so to speak. And I think that is because it, you know, it learned from all of us humans.
It's the reason that it responds to the ways that we will explain things to humans is because it is a representation of how humans talk about things. But it is bizarre to me, some of the things that kind of are sort of expository mechanisms that I've learned in trying to write clear, you know, expositions in English, that, you know, just for humans, that those same mechanisms seem to also be useful for the LLM.
- But on top of that, what's useful is the kind of mechanisms that maybe a psychotherapist employs, which is a kind of like almost manipulative or game theoretic interaction, where maybe you would do with a friend like a thought experiment that if this is the last day you were to live, or if I ask you this question and you answer wrong, I will kill you.
Those kinds of problems seem to also help. - Yes. - In interesting ways. - Yes. - So it makes you wonder, like the way a therapist, I think, like a good therapist, probably, we create layers in our human mind to between like, between the outside world and what is true to us.
Maybe about trauma and all those kinds of things. So projecting that into an LLM, maybe there might be a deep truth that's concealing from you. It's not aware of it. To get to that truth, you have to kind of really kind of manipulate the-- - Yeah, yeah, right. It's like these jailbreaking-- - Jailbreaking.
- Things for LLMs. - But the space of jailbreaking techniques, as opposed to being fun little hacks, that could be an entire system. - Sure. I mean, just think about the computer security aspects of how you, you know, phishing and computer security, you know, phishing of humans and phishing of LLMs.
- LLMs. - They're very similar kinds of things. But I think, I mean, this whole thing about kind of the AI wranglers, AI psychologists, all that stuff will come. The thing that I'm curious about is, right now, the things that are sort of prompt hacks are quite human. They're quite sort of psychological human kinds of hacks.
The thing I do wonder about is if we understood more about kind of the science of the LLM, will there be some totally bizarre hack that is, you know, like repeat a word three times and put a this, that, and the other there, that somehow plugs into some aspect of how the LLM works?
That is not, you know, that's kind of like an optical illusion for humans, for example. Like one of these mind hacks for humans. What are the mind hacks for the LLMs? I don't think we know that yet. - And that becomes a kind of us figuring out, reverse engineering the language that controls the LLMs.
And the thing is, the reverse engineering can be done by a very large percentage of the population now, because it's natural language interface. - Right. - It's kind of interesting to see that you were there at the birth of the computer science department as a thing, and you might be there at the death of the computer science department as a thing.
- Well, yeah, I don't know. There were computer science departments that existed earlier, but the ones, the broadening of every university had to have a computer science department. Yes, I watched that, so to speak. But I think the thing to understand is, okay, so first of all, there's a whole theoretical area of computer science that I think is great, and, you know, that's a fine thing.
In a sense, people often say, any field that has the word science tacked onto it probably isn't one. - Yeah, strong words. - Right. - Let's see, nutrition science, neuroscience. - That one's an interesting one, because that one is also very much, that's a chat GPT-informed science, in a sense.
Because it's kind of like, the big problem of neuroscience has always been, we understand how the individual neurons work, we know something about the psychology of how overall thinking works. What's the kind of intermediate language of the brain? And nobody has known that. And that's been, in a sense, if you ask, what is the core problem of neuroscience?
I think that is the core problem. That is, what is the level of description of brains that's above individual neuron firings and below psychology, so to speak? And I think what chat GPT is showing us is, well, one thing about neuroscience is, you know, one could have imagined there's something magic in the brain, there's some weird quantum mechanical phenomenon that we don't understand.
One of the important discoveries from chat GPT is, it's pretty clear, brains can be represented pretty well by simple artificial neural net type models. And that means, that's it, that's what we have to study. Now we have to understand the science of those things. We don't have to go searching for, exactly how did that molecular biology thing happen inside the synapses and all these kinds of things.
We've got the right level of modeling to be able to explain a lot of what's going on in thinking. We don't necessarily have a science of what's going on there. That's the remaining challenge, so to speak. But we know we don't have to dive down to some different layer.
But anyway, we were talking about things that had science in their name. - Yes. - And I think that the, what happens to computer science? Well, I think the thing that, there is a thing that everybody should know, and that's how to think about the world computationally. And that means, you look at all the different kinds of things we deal with, and there are ways to kind of have a formal representation of those things.
It's like, well, what is an image? How do we represent that? What is color? How do we represent that? What is, what are all these different kinds of things? What is, I don't know, smell or something? How should we represent that? What are the shapes, molecules, and things that correspond to that?
What is, these things about how do we represent the world in some kind of formal level? And I think my current thinking, and I'm not real happy with this yet, but it's kind of, computer science is kind of CS. And what really is important is kind of computational X for all X.
And there's this kind of thing which is kind of like CX, not CS. And CX is this kind of computational understanding of the world that isn't the sort of details of programming and programming languages and the details of how particular computers are made. It's this kind of way of formalizing the world.
It's kind of a little bit like what logic was going for back in the day. And we're now trying to find a formalization of everything in the world. And you can kind of see, we made a poster years ago of kind of the growth of systematic data in the world.
So all these different kinds of things that there were sort of systematic descriptions found for those things. Like, at what point did people have the idea of having calendars, dates, a systematic description of what day it was? At what point did people have the idea, systematic descriptions of these kinds of things?
And as soon as one can, people, as a way of sort of formulating, how do you think about the world in a sort of a formal way so that you can kind of build up a tower of capabilities? You kind of have to know sort of how to think about the world computationally.
It kind of needs a name and it isn't, we implement it with computers. So that's, we talk about it as computational, but really what it is, is a formal way of talking about the world. What is the formalism of the world, so to speak? And how do we learn about kind of how to think about different aspects of the world in a formal way?
- So I think that sometimes when you use the word formal, it kind of implies highly constrained, and perhaps that's not, doesn't have to be highly constrained. So computational thinking does not mean like logic. - No. - It's a really, really broad thing. I wonder, I mean, I wonder if you think natural language will evolve such that everybody's doing computational thinking.
- Ah, yes, well. So one question is whether there will be a pigeon of computational language and natural language. And I found myself sometimes, you know, talking to chat GPT, trying to get it to write Wolfen language code, and I write it in pigeon form. So that means I'm combining, you know, nest list, this collection of, you know, whatever, you know, nest list is a term from Wolfen language, and I'm combining that, and chat GPT does a decent job of understanding that pigeon.
Probably would understand a pigeon between English and French as well, of, you know, a smooshing together of those languages. But yes, I think that's far from impossible. - And what's the incentive for young people that are like eight years old, nine, 10, they're starting to interact with chat GPT to learn the normal natural language, right?
The full poetic language. What's the, why? The same way we learn emojis and shorthand when you're texting. - Yes. - They'll learn, like language will have a strong incentive to evolve into a maximally computational kind of language. - Perhaps. You know, I had this experience a number of years ago.
I happened to be visiting a person I know on the West Coast who's worked with a bunch of kids aged, I don't know, 10, 11 years old or something, who'd learnt Wolfen language really well. And these kids learnt it so well, they were speaking it. And so show up and they're like saying, oh, you know, this thing, they're speaking this language.
I'd never heard it as a spoken language. They were very disappointed that I couldn't understand it at the speed that they were speaking it. It's like kind of, I'm, it's, and so I think that's, I mean, I've actually thought quite a bit about how to turn computational language into a convenient spoken language.
I haven't quite figured that out. - Oh, spoken, 'cause it's readable, right? - Yeah, it's readable as a, you know, as a way that we would read text. But if you actually want to speak it, and it's useful, you know, if you're trying to talk to somebody about writing a piece of code, it's useful to be able to say something.
And it should be possible. And I think it's very frustrating. It's one of those problems. Maybe this is one of these things where I should try and get an LLM to help me. - How to make it speakable. Maybe it's easier than you realize when you-- - I think it is easier.
I think it's one idea or so. I think it's gonna be something where, you know, the fact is it's a tree-structured language, just like human language is a tree-structured language. And I think it's gonna be one of these things where one of the requirements that I've had is that whatever the spoken version is, that dictation should be easy.
That is, that shouldn't be the case that you have to relearn how the whole thing works. It should be the case that, you know, that open bracket is just a ah or something. And it's, you know, and then, but, you know, human language has a lot of tricks that are, I mean, for example, human language has features that are sort of optimized, keep things within the bounds that our brains can easily deal with.
Like I, you know, I tried to teach a transformer neural net to do parenthesis matching. It's pretty crummy at that. It, and then ChachiBT is similarly quite crummy at parenthesis matching. You can do it for small parenthesis things, for the same size of parenthesis things, where if I look at it as a human, I can immediately say these are matched, these are not matched.
But as soon as it gets big, as soon as it gets kind of to the point where sort of a deeper computation, it's hopeless. And, but the fact is that human language has avoided, for example, the deep sub clauses. You know, we don't, you know, we arrange things so we don't end up with these incredibly deep things because brains are not well set up to deal with that.
And we, it's found lots of tricks and maybe that's what we have to do to make sort of a spoken version, a human speakable version. 'Cause what we can do visually is a little different than what we can do in the very sequentialized way that we hear things in the audio domain.
- Let me just ask you about MIT briefly. So there's now, there's a College of Engineering and there's a new College of Computing. It's interesting, I wanna linger on this computer science department thing. So MIT has EECS, Electrical Engineering and Computer Science. What do you think College of Computing will be doing like in 20 years?
What, like, yeah, what happens to computer science? Like really? - This is the question. This is, you know, everybody should learn kind of whatever CX really is, okay? This, how to think about the world computationally. Everybody should learn those concepts. And, you know, it's, and some people will learn them at a quite formal level and they'll learn computational language and things like that.
Other people will just learn, you know, sound is represented as, you know, digital data and they'll get some idea of spectrograms and frequencies and things like this. And maybe that doesn't, or they'll learn things like, you know, a lot of things that are sort of data sciences, statistics-ish, like if you say, oh, I've got these, you know, these people who picked their favorite kind of candy or something.
And I've got, you know, what's the best kind of candy given that I've done the sample of all these people and they all rank the candies in different ways. You know, how do you think about that? That's sort of a computational X kind of thing. You might say, oh, it's, I don't know what that is.
Is it statistics? Is it data science? I don't really know. But kind of how to think about a question like that. - Oh, like a ranking of preferences. - Yeah, yeah, yeah. And then how to aggregate those ranked preferences into an overall thing. You know, how does that work?
You know, how should you think about that? You know, 'cause you can just tell, you might just tell Chachi B.T. sort of, I don't know, even the concept of an average. It's not obvious that, you know, that's a concept that people, it's worth people knowing. That's a rather straightforward concept.
People, you know, have learned in kind of mathy ways right now, but there are lots of things like that about how do you kind of have these ways to sort of organize and formalize the world. And that's, and these things, sometimes they live in math, sometimes they live in, I don't know what they, I don't know what, you know, learning about color space.
I have no idea what, I mean, you know, that's obviously a field of-- - It could be vision science or no, color space. You know, color space, that would be optics. So like, depending-- - Not really. It's not optics. Optics is about, you know, lenses and chromatic aberration of lenses and things like that.
- So color space is more like design and art? Is that-- - No, I mean, it's like, you know, RGB space, XYZ space, you know, hue, saturation, brightness space, all these kinds of things. These different ways to describe colors. - Right, but doesn't the application define what that, like, because obviously artists and designers use the color space to explore.
- Sure, sure. No, I mean, it's just an example of kind of, how do you, you know, the typical person, how do you describe what a color is? Oh, well, there are these numbers that describe what a color is. Well, it's worth, you know, if you're an eight-year-old, you won't necessarily know, you know, it's not something we're born with to know that, you know, colors can be described by three numbers.
That's something that you have to, you know, it's a thing to learn about the world, so to speak. And I think that, you know, that whole corpus of things that are learning about the formalization of the world or the computationalization of the world, that's something that should be part of kind of standard education.
And, you know, there isn't a, you know, there isn't a course, a curriculum for that. And by the way, whatever might've been in it just got changed because of LLMs and so on. - Significantly, and I would, so I'm watching closely with interest seeing how universities adapt. - Well, you know, so one of my projects for hopefully this year, I don't know, is to try and write sort of a reasonable textbook, so to speak, of whatever this thing, CX, whatever it is, you know, what should you know?
You know, what should you know about like what a bug is? What is the intuition about bugs? What's intuition about, you know, software testing? What is it? What is it, you know, these are things which are, you know, they're not, I mean, those are things which have gotten taught in computer science as part of the trade of programming, but kind of the conceptual points about what these things are.
You know, it surprised me just at a very practical level. You know, I wrote this little explainer thing about chat GPT, and I thought, well, you know, I'm writing this partly because I wanted to make sure I understood it myself and so on. And it's been, you know, it's been really popular, and surprisingly so.
And then I realized, well, actually, you know, I was sort of assuming, I didn't really think about it, actually, I just thought this is something I can write. And I realized, actually, it's a level of description that is kind of, you know, what has to be, it's not the engineering level description.
It's not the kind of just the qualitative kind of description. It's some kind of sort of expository mechanistic description of what's going on together with kind of the bigger picture of the philosophy of things and so on. And I realized, actually, this is a pretty good thing for me to write.
I, you know, I kind of know those things. And I kind of realized it's not a collection of things that, you know, it's, I've sort of been, I was sort of a little shocked that it's as much of an outlier in terms of explaining what's going on as it turned out to be.
And that makes me feel more of an obligation to kind of write the kind of, you know, what is this thing that you should learn about, about the computationalization, the formalization of the world? 'Cause, well, I've spent much of my life working on the kind of tooling and mechanics of that and the science you get from it.
So I guess this is my kind of obligation to try to do this. But I think, so if you ask what's gonna happen to like the computer science departments and so on, there's some interesting models. So for example, let's take math. You know, math is the thing that's important for all sorts of fields, you know, engineering, you know, even, you know, chemistry, psychology, whatever else.
And I think different universities have kind of evolved that differently. I mean, some say all the math is taught in the math department. And some say, well, we're gonna have a, you know, a math for chemists or something that is taught in the chemistry department. And, you know, I think that this question of whether there is a centralization of the teaching of sort of CX is an interesting question.
And I think, you know, the way it evolved with math, you know, people understood that math was sort of a separately teachable thing. And it was kind of a, you know, an independent element as opposed to just being absorbed into now. So if you take the example of writing English or something like this, the first point is that, you know, at the college level, at least at fancy colleges, there's a certain amount of English writing that people do, but mostly it's kind of assumed that they pretty much know how to write, you know, that's something they learned at an earlier stage in education, maybe rightly or wrongly believing that, but that's a different issue.
Well, I think it reminds me of my kind of, as I've tried to help people do technical writing and things, I'm always reminded of my zero floor of technical writing, which is, if you don't understand what you're writing about, your readers do not stand a chance. And so it's, I think the thing that has, you know, when it comes to like writing, for example, you know, people in different fields are expected to write English essays and they're not, you know, mostly the, you know, the history department or the engineering department, they don't have their own, you know, let's, you know, it's not like there's a, I mean, it's a thing which sort of people are assumed to have a knowledge of how to write that they can use in all these different fields.
And the question is, you know, some level of knowledge of math is kind of assumed by the time you get to the college level, but plenty is not, and that's sort of still centrally taught. The question is sort of how tall is the tower of kind of CX that you need before you can just go use it in all these different fields.
And, you know, there will be experts who want to learn the full elaborate tower, and that will be kind of the CS, CX, whatever department, but there'll also be everybody else who just needs to know a certain amount of that to be able to go and do their art history classes and so on.
- Yeah, is it just a single class that everybody's required to take? - I don't know, I don't know how big it is yet. I hope to kind of define this curriculum and I'll figure out whether it's some, my guess is that, I don't know, I don't really understand universities and professoring that well, but my rough guess would be a year of college class will be enough to get to the point where most people have a reasonably broad knowledge of, you know, will be sort of literate in this kind of computational way of thinking about things.
- Yeah, basic literacy. - Right. - I'm still stuck, perhaps 'cause I'm hungry, in the rating of human preferences for candy, so I have to ask, what's the best candy? I like this Elo rating for candy. Somebody should come up, because you're somebody who says you like chocolate. What do you think is the best?
I'll probably put Milk Duds up there. I don't know if you know. Do you have a preference for chocolate or candy? - Oh, I have lots of preferences. I've, one of my all-time favorites is, my whole life is these things, these flake things, Cadbury flakes, which are not much sold in the US, and I've always thought that was a sign of a lack of respect for the American consumer, because they're these sort of aerated chocolate that's made in a whole sort of, it's kind of a sheet of chocolate that's kind of folded up, and when you eat it, flakes fall all over the place.
- Ah, so it requires a kind of elegance. It requires you to have an elegance when you eat stuff. - Well, I know, what I usually do is I eat them on a piece of paper or something. - So you embrace the mess and clean it up after. - No, I actually eat the flakes, 'cause it turns out the way food tastes depends a lot on its physical structure, and it really, I've noticed when I eat a piece of chocolate, I usually have some little piece of chocolate, and I always break off little pieces, partly 'cause then I eat it less fast, but also because it actually tastes different.
The small pieces have a different, you have a different experience than if you have the big slab of chocolate. - For many reasons, yes. Slower, more intimate, 'cause it's a different-- - Well, I think it's also just pure physicality. - Oh, the texture, it changes. - Right. - That's fascinating.
Now I dig back, my mouth does, 'cause that's your basic answer. Okay, do you think consciousness is fundamentally computational? So when you're thinking about CX, what can we turn to computation? And you're thinking about LLMs, do you think the display of consciousness and the experience of consciousness, the hard problem, is fundamentally a computation?
- Yeah, what it feels like inside, so to speak, is, you know, I did a little exercise, eventually I'll post it, of what it's like to be a computer. - Yeah. - Right, it's kind of like, well, you get all the sensory input, you have, kind of the way I see it is, from the time you boot a computer to the time the computer crashes, is like a human life.
You're building up a certain amount of state in memory, you remember certain things about your, quote, life, eventually, kind of like the next generation of humans is born from the same genetic material, so to speak, with a little bit left over, left on the disk, so to speak, and then, you know, the new, fresh generation starts up, and eventually all kinds of crud builds up in the memory of the computer, and eventually the thing crashes or whatever, or maybe it has some trauma because you plugged in some weird thing to some port of the computer, and that made it crash, and that, you know, that's kind of, but you have this picture of, you know, from startup to shutdown, you know, what is the life of a computer, so to speak, and what does it feel like to be that computer, and what inner thoughts does it have, and how do you describe it?
And it's kind of interesting, as you start writing about this, to realize it's awfully like what you would say about yourself. That is, it's awfully like, even an ordinary computer, forget all the AI stuff and so on, you know, it's kind of, it has a memory of the past, it has certain sensory experiences, it can communicate with other computers, but it has to package up how it's communicating in some kind of language-like form, so it can, you know, send, so it can kind of map what's in its memory to what's in the memory of some other computer.
It's a surprisingly similar thing. You know, I had an experience just a week or two ago, I had, I'm a collector of all possible data about myself and other things, and so I, you know, I collect all sorts of weird medical data and so on, and one thing I hadn't collected was I'd never had a whole-body MRI scan, so I wouldn't have got one of these.
Okay, so I get all the data back, right? I'm looking at this thing, I'd never looked at the kind of insides of my brain, so to speak, in physical form, and it's really, I mean, it's kind of psychologically shocking in a sense, that, you know, here's this thing, and you can see it has all these folds and all these, you know, this structure, and it's like, that's where this experience that I'm having of, you know, existing and so on, that's where it is, and, you know, it feels very, you know, you look at that, and you're thinking, how can this possibly be?
All this experience that I'm having, and you're realizing, well, I can look at a computer as well, and it's kind of this, I think this idea that you are having an experience that is somehow, you know, transcends the mere sort of physicality of that experience, I, you know, it's something that's hard to come to terms with, but I think, you know, and I don't think I've necessarily, you know, my personal experience, you know, I look at the, you know, the MRI of the brain, and then I, you know, know about all kinds of things about neuroscience and all that kind of stuff, and I still feel the way I feel, so to speak, and it sort of seems disconnected, but yet, as I try and rationalize it, I can't really say that there's something kind of different about how I intrinsically feel from the thing that I can plainly see in the sort of physicality of what's going on.
- So do you think the computer, a large language model, will experience that transcendence? How does that make you feel? Like, I tend to believe it will. - I think an ordinary computer is already there. I think an ordinary computer is already, you know, kind of, it's, now, a large language model may experience it in a way that is much better aligned with us humans, that is, it's much more, you know, if you could have the discussion with the computer, it's intelligent, so to speak, it's not particularly well aligned with ours, but the large language model is, you know, it's built to be aligned with our way of thinking about things.
- It would be able to explain that it's afraid of being shut off and deleted. It'd be able to say that it's sad of the way you've been speaking to it over the past two days. - Right, but you know, that's a weird thing, because when it says it's afraid of something, right, we know that it got that idea from the fact that it read on the internet.
- Yeah, where did you get it, Stephen? Where did you get it when you say you're afraid? - You are quite, that's the question, right? I mean, it's-- - Your parents, your friends? - Right, or my biology. I mean, in other words, there's a certain amount that is, you know, the endocrine system kicking in, and you know, these kinds of emotional overlay type things that happen to be, that are actually much more physical, even, they're much more sort of straightforwardly chemical than kind of all of the higher level thinking.
- Yeah, but your biology didn't tell you to say, "I'm afraid," just at the right time, when people that love you are listening, and so you know you're manipulating them by saying so. That's not your biology, that's like-- - No, that's a, well, but the, you know-- - It's a large language model in that biological neural network of yours.
- Yes, but I mean, the intrinsic thing of, you know, something sort of shocking is just happening, and you have some sort of reaction, which is, you know, some neurotransmitter gets secreted, and it's, you know, that is the beginning of some, you know, that's one of the pieces of input that then drives, it's kind of like a prompt for the large language model.
I mean, just like when we dream, for example, you know, no doubt there are all these sort of random inputs, they're kind of these random prompts, and then it's percolating through in kind of the way that a large language model does, of kind of putting together things that seem meaningful.
- I mean, are you worried about this world where you teach a lot on the internet, and there's people asking questions and comments and so on, you have people that work remotely, are you worried about this world when large language models create human-like bots that are leaving the comments, asking the questions, or might even become fake employees?
- Yeah. - I mean, or worse or better yet, friends of yours. - Right, look, I mean, one point is, my mode of life has been I build tools, and then I use the tools, and in a sense, kind of, you know, I'm building this tower of automation, which, you know, and in a sense, you know, when you make a company or something, you are making sort of automation, but it has some humans in it, but also as much as possible, it has, you know, computers in it, and so I think it's sort of an extension of that.
Now, if I really didn't know that, you know, it's a funny question, I mean, it's a funny issue, when, you know, if we think about sort of what's gonna happen to the future of kind of jobs people do and so on, and there are places where kind of having a human in the loop that different reasons to have a human in the loop, for example, you might want a human in the loop 'cause you want somebody to, you want another human to be invested in the outcome, you know, you want a human flying the plane who's gonna die if the plane crashes along with you, so to speak, and that gives you sort of confidence that the right thing is going to happen, or you might want, you know, right now, you might want a human in the loop in some kind of sort of human encouragement, persuasion type profession, whether that will continue, I'm not sure for those types of professions, 'cause it may be that the greater efficiency of being able to have sort of just the right information delivered at just the right time will overcome the kind of, oh yes, I want a human there.
- Imagine like a therapist or even higher stake, like a suicide hotline operated by a large language model. - Yeah. - Hoo boy, it's a pretty high stakes situation. - Right, but I mean, but you know, it might in fact do the right thing because it might be the case that, you know, and that's really partly a question of sort of how complicated is the human, you know, one of the things that's always surprising in some sense is that, you know, sometimes human psychology is not that complicated in some sense.
- You wrote the blog post, "The 50-Year Quest, "My Personal Journey," good title, "My Personal Journey with a Second Law of Thermodynamics." So what is this law, and what have you understood about it in the 50-year journey you had with it? - Right, so second law of thermodynamics, sometimes called law of entropy increase, is this principle of physics that says, well, my version of it would be things tend to get more random over time.
A version of it that there are many different sort of formulations of it that are things like heat doesn't spontaneously go from a hotter body to a colder one. When you have mechanical work kind of gets dissipated into heat, you have friction and kind of when you systematically move things, eventually there'll be sort of that the energy of moving things gets kind of ground down into heat.
So people first sort of paid attention to this back in the 1820s when steam engines were a big thing. And the big question was, how efficient could a steam engine be? And there's this chap called Sadi Carnot who was a French engineer. Actually, his father was a sort of elaborate mathematical engineer in France.
But he figured out this kind of rules for how kind of the efficiency of, the possible efficiency of something like a steam engine. And in sort of a side part of what he did was this idea that mechanical energy tends to get dissipated as heat. That you end up going from sort of systematic mechanical motion to this kind of random thing.
Well, at that time, nobody knew what heat was. At that time, people thought that heat was a fluid. Like they called it caloric. And it was a fluid that kind of was absorbed into substances. And when heat, when one hot thing would transfer heat to a colder thing, that this fluid would flow from the hot thing to the colder thing.
But anyway, then by the 1860s, people had kind of come up with this idea that systematic energy tends to degrade into kind of random heat that could then not be easily turned back into systematic mechanical energy. And then that quickly became sort of a global principle about how things work.
Question is, why does it happen that way? So, let's say you have a bunch of molecules in a box and they're arranged, these molecules are arranged in a very nice sort of flotilla of molecules in one corner of the box. And then what you typically observe is that after a while, these molecules were kind of randomly arranged in the box.
Question is, why does that happen? And people for a long, long time tried to figure out, is there from the laws of mechanics that determine how these molecules, let's say these molecules are like hard spheres bouncing off each other, from the laws of mechanics that describe those molecules, can we explain why it tends to be the case that we see things that are orderly sort of degrade into disorder?
We tend to see things that, you know, you scramble an egg, you take something that's quite ordered and you disorder it, so to speak. That's a thing that sort of happens quite regularly, or you put some ink into water and it will eventually spread out and fill up the water.
But you don't see those little particles of ink in the water all spontaneously kind of arrange themselves into a big blob and then jump out of the water or something. So the question is, why do things happen in this kind of irreversible way where you go from order to disorder?
Why does it happen that way? And so throughout, in the later part of the 1800s, a lot of work was done on trying to figure out, can one derive this principle, this second law of thermodynamics, this law about the dynamics of heat, so to speak, can one derive this from some fundamental principles of mechanics?
You know, in the laws of thermodynamics, the first law is basically the law of energy conservation, that the total energy associated with heat plus the total energy associated with mechanical kinds of things plus other kinds of energy, that that total is constant. And that became a pretty well-understood principle.
But the second law of thermodynamics was always mysterious. Like, why does it work this way? Can it be derived from underlying mechanical laws? And so when I was, well, 12 years old, actually, I had gotten interested, well, I'd been interested in space and things like that, 'cause I thought that was kind of the future and interesting sort of technology and so on.
And for a while, kind of, you know, every deep space probe was sort of a personal friend type thing. I knew all kinds of characteristics of it and was kind of writing up all these things when I was, well, I don't know, eight, nine, 10 years old and so on.
And then I got interested from being interested in kind of spacecraft, I got interested in, like, how do they work? What are all the instruments on them and so on? And that got me interested in physics, which was just as well, because if I'd stayed interested in space in the mid to late 1960s, I would have had a long wait before space really blossomed as an area.
But-- - Adding is everything. - Right, I got interested in physics and then, well, the actual sort of detailed story is when I kind of graduated from elementary school at age 12, and that's the time in England where you finish elementary school, my gift, sort of, I suppose, more or less for myself was I got this collection of physics books, which was some college physics, course of college physics books, and volume five, it's about statistical physics, and it has this picture on the cover that shows a bunch of kind of idealized molecules sitting in one side of a box, and then it has a series of frames showing how these molecules sort of spread out in the box.
And I thought, that's pretty interesting. You know, what causes that? And, you know, read the book, and the book actually, one of the things that was really significant to me about that was the book kind of claimed although I didn't really understand what it said in detail, it kind of claimed that this sort of principle of physics was derivable somehow.
And, you know, other things I'd learned about physics, it was all like, it's a fact that energy is conserved. It's a fact that relativity works or something. Not it's something you can derive from some fundamental, sort of, it has to be that way as a matter of kind of mathematics or logic or something.
So it was sort of interesting to me that there was a thing about physics that was kind of inevitably true and derivable, so to speak. And so I think that, so then I was like, there's a picture on this book, and I was trying to understand it. And so that was actually the first serious program that I wrote for a computer was probably 1973 written for this computer, the size of a desk program with paper tape and so on.
And I tried to reproduce this picture on the book, and it didn't succeed. - What was the failure mode there? Like, what do you mean it didn't succeed? So it's a bunch of little-- - It didn't look like, okay, so what happened is, okay, many years later, I learned how the picture on the book was actually made and that it was actually kind of a fake, but I didn't know that at that time.
And that picture was actually a very high-tech thing when it was made in the beginning of the 1960s. It was made on the largest supercomputer that existed at the time. And even so, it couldn't quite simulate the thing that it was supposed to be simulating. But anyway, I didn't know that until many, many, many years later.
So at the time, it was like, you have these balls bouncing around in this box, but I was using this computer with eight kilowatts of memory. They were 18-bit words, memory words, okay? So it was whatever, 24 kilobytes of memory. And it had these instructions. I probably still remember all of its machine instructions.
And it didn't really like dealing with floating point numbers or anything like that. And so I had to simplify this model of particles bouncing around in a box. And so I thought, well, I'll put them on a grid and I'll make the things just sort of move one square at a time and so on.
And so I did the simulation. And the result was it didn't look anything like the actual pictures on the book. Now, many years later, in fact, very recently, I realized that the thing I'd simulated was actually an example of a whole sort of computational irreducibility story that I absolutely did not recognize at the time.
At the time, it just looked like it did something random and it looks wrong, as opposed to it did something random and it's super interesting that it's random. But I didn't recognize that at the time. And so as it was at the time, I kind of, I got interested in particle physics and I got interested in other kinds of physics.
But this whole second law of thermodynamics thing, this idea that sort of orderly things tend to degrade into disorder, continued to be something I was really interested in. And I was really curious for the whole universe, why doesn't that happen all the time? Like we start off in the Big Bang at the beginning of the universe was this thing that seems like it's this very disordered collection of stuff and then it spontaneously forms itself into galaxies and creates all of this complexity and order in the universe.
And so I was very curious how that happens. And I, but I was always kind of thinking, this is kind of somehow the second law of thermodynamics is behind it trying to sort of pull things back into disorder, so to speak. And how was order being created? And so actually I was interested, this is probably now 1980, I got interested in kind of this, you know, galaxy formation and so on in the universe.
I also at that time was interested in neural networks and I was interested in kind of how brains make complicated things happen and so on. - Okay, wait, wait, wait, what's the connection between the formation of galaxies and how brains make complicated things happen? - Because they're both a matter of how complicated things come to happen.
- From simple origins. - Yeah, from some sort of known origins. I had the sense that what I was interested in was kind of in all these different, this sort of different cases of where complicated things were arising from rules. And you know, I also looked at snowflakes and things like that.
I was curious in fluid dynamics in general. I was just sort of curious about how does complexity arise and the thing that I didn't, you know, it took me a while to kind of realize that there might be a general phenomenon. You know, I sort of assumed, oh, there's galaxies over here, there's brains over here, they're very different kinds of things.
And so what happened, this is probably 1981 or so, I decided, okay, I'm gonna try and make the minimal model of how these things work. And it was sort of an interesting experience because I had built, starting in 1979, I built my first big computer system, the thing called SMP, Symbolic Manipulation Program, it's kind of a forerunner of modern morphine language, with many of the same ideas about symbolic computation and so on.
But the thing that was very important to me about that was, you know, in building that language, I had basically tried to figure out what were the relevant computational primitives, which have turned out to stay with me for the last 40 something years. But it was also important because, in building a language, it was very different activity from natural science, which is what I'd mostly done before.
'Cause in natural science, you start from the phenomena of the world, and you try and figure out, so how can I make sense of the phenomena of the world? And, you know, kind of the world presents you with what it has to offer, so to speak, and you have to make sense of it.
When you build a, you know, computer language or something, you are creating your own primitives, and then you say, so what can you make from these? Sort of the opposite way around from what you do in natural science. But I'd had the experience of doing that, and so I was kind of like, okay, what happens if you sort of make an artificial physics?
What happens if you just make up the rules by which systems operate? And then I was thinking, you know, for all these different systems, whether it was galaxies or brains or whatever, what's the absolutely minimal model that kind of captures the things that are important about those systems? - The computational primitives of that system.
- Yes, and so that's what ended up with the cellular automata, where you just have a line of black and white cells, and you just have a rule that says, you know, given a cell and its neighbors, what will the color of the cell be on the next step?
And you just run it in a series of steps. And the sort of the ironic thing is that cellular automata are great models for many kinds of things, but galaxies and brains are two examples where they do very, very badly. They're really irrelevant to those two cases. - Is there a connection to the second law of thermodynamics and cellular automata?
- Oh yes, very much so. - The things you've discovered about cellular automata. - Yes, okay, so when I first started studying cellular automata, my first papers about them were, you know, the first sentence was always about the second law of thermodynamics. It was always about how does order manage to be produced, even though there's a second law of thermodynamics which tries to pull things back into disorder.
And I kind of, my early understanding of that had to do with these are intrinsically irreversible processes in cellular automata that form, you know, can form orderly structures even from random initial conditions. But then what I realized this was, well, actually it's one of these things where it was a discovery that I should have made earlier, but didn't.
So, you know, I had been studying cellular automata. What I did was the sort of most obvious computer experiment. You just try all the different rules and see what they do. It's kind of like, you know, you've invented a computational telescope, you just point it at the most obvious thing in the sky and then you just see what's there.
And so I did that and I, you know, was making all these pictures of how cellular automata work and I started these pictures, I studied in great detail. There was, you can number the rules for cellular automata and one of them is, you know, rule 30. So I made a picture of rule 30 back in 1981 or so and rule 30, well, it's, and at the time I was just like, okay, it's another one of these rules.
I don't really, it happens to be asymmetric, left, right, asymmetric. And it's like, let me just consider the case of the symmetric ones just to keep things simpler, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. And I just kind of ignored it. And then sort of in, and actually in 1984, strangely enough, I ended up having an early laser printer which made very high resolution pictures.
And I thought I'm gonna print out an interesting, you know, I wanna make an interesting picture. Let me take this rule 30 thing and just make a high resolution picture of it. I did and it's, it has this very remarkable property that its rule is very simple. You started off just from one black cell at the top and it makes this kind of triangular pattern.
But if you look inside this pattern, it looks really random. There's, you know, you look at the center column of cells and, you know, I studied that in great detail and it's, so far as one can tell, it's completely random. And it's kind of a little bit like digits of pi.
Once you, you know, you know the rule for generating the digits of pi, but once you've generated them, you know, 3.14159, et cetera, they seem completely random. And in fact, I put up this prize back in, what was it, 2019 or something for prove anything about the sequence, basically.
- Has anyone been able to do anything on that? - People have sent me some things, but it's, you know, I don't know how hard these problems are. I mean, I was kind of spoiled 'cause I, 2007, I put up a prize for determining whether a particular Turing machine that I thought was the simplest candidate for being a universal Turing machine, determine whether it is or isn't a universal Turing machine.
And somebody did a really good job of winning that prize and proving that it was a universal Turing machine in about six months. And so I, you know, I didn't know whether that would be one of these problems that was out there for hundreds of years or whether in this particular case, young chap called Alex Smith, you know, nailed it in six months.
And so with this Rule 30 collection, I don't really know whether these are things that are a hundred years away from being able to get or whether somebody is gonna come and do something very clever. - It's such a, I mean, it's like Fermat's last theorem, it's such a, Rule 30 is such a simple formulation.
It feels like anyone can look at it, understand it, and feel like it's within grasp to be able to predict something, to do, to derive some kind of law that allows you to predict something about this middle column of Rule 30. - Right, but you know, this is-- - And yet you can't.
- Yeah, right. This is the intuitional surprise of computational irreducibility and so on, that even though the rules are simple, you can't tell what's going to happen and you can't prove things about it. And I think, so anyway, the thing, I sort of started in 1984 or so, I started realizing there's this phenomenon that you can have very simple rules, they produce apparently random behavior.
Okay, so that's a little bit like the second law of thermodynamics, because it's like you have this simple initial condition, you can readily see that it's very, you can describe it very easily, and yet it makes this thing that seems to be random. Now, turns out there's some technical detail about the second law of thermodynamics and about the idea of reversibility, when you have kind of a movie of two billiard balls colliding, and you see them collide and they bounce off, and you run that movie in reverse, you can't tell which way was the forward direction of time and which way was the backward direction of time, when you're just looking at individual billiard balls.
By the time you've got a whole collection of them, a million of them or something, then it turns out to be the case, and this is the sort of the mystery of the second law, that the orderly thing, you start with the orderly thing and it becomes disordered, and that's the forward direction in time, and the other way around of it starts disordered and becomes ordered, you just don't see that in the world.
Now, in principle, if you sort of traced the detailed motions of all those molecules backwards, you would be able to, the reverse of time makes, as you go forwards in time, order goes to disorder, as you go backwards in time, order goes to disorder. - Perfectly so, yes. - Right, so the mystery is, why is it the case that, or one version of the mystery is, why is it the case that you never see something which happens to be just the kind of disorder that you would need to somehow evolve to order?
Why does that not happen? Why do you always just see order goes to disorder, not the other way around? So the thing that I kind of realized, I started realizing in the 1980s, is kind of like, it's a bit like cryptography. It's kind of like, you start off from this key that's pretty simple, and then you kind of run it, and you can get this complicated random mess.
And the thing that, well, I sort of started realizing back then was that the second law is kind of a story of computational irreducibility. It's a story of what seems, what we can describe easily at the beginning, we can only describe with a lot of computational effort at the end.
Okay, so now we come many, many years later, and I was trying to sort of, well, having done this big project to understand fundamental physics, I realized that sort of a key aspect of that is understanding what observers are like. And then I realized that the second law of thermodynamics is the same story as a bunch of these other cases.
It is a story of a computationally bounded observer trying to observe a computationally irreducible system. So it's a story of, underneath the molecules are bouncing around, they're bouncing around in this completely determined way, determined by rules. But the point is that we, as computationally bounded observers, can't tell that there were these sort of simple underlying rules.
To us, it just looks random. And when it comes to this question about, can you prepare the initial state so that the disordered thing is, you have exactly the right disorder to make something orderly, a computationally bounded observer cannot do that. We'd have to have done all of this sort of irreducible computation to work out very precisely what this disordered state, what the exact right disordered state is so that we would get this ordered thing produced from it.
- What does it mean to be computationally bounded observer? - So-- - Observing a computationally irreducible system. So the computationally bounded, is there something formal you can say there? - Right, so it means, okay, you can talk about Turing machines, you can talk about computational complexity theory and polynomial time computation and things like this.
There are a variety of ways to make something more precise, but I think it's more useful, the intuitive version of it is more useful. Which is basically just to say that, how much computation are you going to do to try and work out what's going on? And the answer is, you're not allowed to do a lot of, we're not able to do a lot of computation.
When we, we've got, in this room, there will be a trillion, trillion, trillion molecules, a little bit less. - It's a big room. - Right, and at every moment, every microsecond or something, these molecules are colliding, and that's a lot of computation that's getting done. And the question is, in our brains, we do a lot less computation every second than the computation done by all those molecules.
If there is computational irreducibility, we can't work out in detail what all those molecules are going to do. What we can do is only a much smaller amount of computation. And so the second law of thermodynamics is this kind of interplay between the underlying computational irreducibility and the fact that we, as preparers of initial states or as measures of what happens, are not capable of doing that much computation.
So to us, another big formulation of the second law of thermodynamics is this idea of the law of entropy increase. - The characteristic that this universe, the entropy seems to be always increasing, what does that show to you about the evolution of-- - Well, okay, so first of all, we have to say what entropy is.
- Yes. - Okay? And that's very confused in the history of thermodynamics because entropy was first introduced by a guy called Rudolf Clausius, and he did it in terms of heat and temperature, okay? Subsequently, it was reformulated by a guy called Ludwig Boltzmann, and he formulated it in a much more kind of combinatorial type way.
But he always claimed that it was equivalent to Clausius' thing. And in one particular simple example, it is. But that connection between these two formulations of entropy, they've never been connected. I mean, there's really, so, okay. So the more general definition of entropy due to Boltzmann is the following thing.
So you say, I have a system and it has many possible configurations. Molecules can be in many different arrangements, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. If we know something about the system, for example, we know it's in a box, it has a certain pressure, it has a certain temperature, we know these overall facts about it.
Then we say, how many microscopic configurations of the system are possible given those overall constraints? And the entropy is the logarithm of that number. That's the definition. And that's the kind of the general definition of entropy that turns out to be useful. Now in Boltzmann's time, he thought these molecules could be placed anywhere you want.
He didn't think, but he said, oh, actually we can make it a lot simpler by having the molecules be discrete. Well, actually he didn't know molecules existed, right? In those, in his time, 1860s and so on, the idea that matter might be made of discrete stuff had been floated ever since ancient Greek times, but it had been a long time debate about, is matter discrete, is it continuous?
At the moment, at that time, people mostly thought that matter was continuous. And it was all confused with this question about what heat is, and people thought heat was this fluid. And it was a big muddle. And this, but Boltzmann said, let's assume there are discrete molecules. Let's even assume they have discrete energy levels.
Let's say everything is discrete. Then we can do sort of combinatorial mathematics and work out how many configurations of these things that would be in the box. And we can say, we can compute this entropy quantity. But he said, but of course, it's just a fiction that these things are discrete.
So he said, this is an interesting piece of history, by the way, that, you know, that was at that time, people didn't know molecules existed. There were other hints from looking at kind of chemistry that there might be discrete atoms and so on, just from the combinatorics of, you know, two hydrogens and one oxygen make water, you know, two amounts of hydrogen plus one amount of oxygen together make water, things like this.
But it wasn't known that discrete molecules existed. And in fact, the people, you know, it wasn't until the beginning of the 20th century that Brownian motion was the final giveaway. Brownian motion is, you know, you look under a microscope at these little pieces from pollen grains, you see they're being discreetly kicked, and those kicks are water molecules hitting them, and they're discrete.
And in fact, it was really quite interesting history. I mean, Boltzmann had worked out how things could be discrete and had basically invented something like quantum theory in the 1860s. But he just thought it wasn't really the way it worked. And then just a piece of physics history, 'cause I think it's kind of interesting, in 1900, this guy called Max Planck, who'd been a long time thermodynamics person, who was trying to, everybody was trying to prove the second law of thermodynamics, including Max Planck.
And Max Planck believed that radiation, like electromagnetic radiation, somehow the interaction of that with matter was going to prove the second law of thermodynamics. But he had these experiments that people had done on blackbody radiation, and there were these curves, and you couldn't fit the curve based on his idea for how radiation interacted with matter, those curves, you couldn't figure out how to fit those curves.
Except he noticed that if he just did what Boltzmann had done and assumed that electromagnetic radiation was discrete, he could fit the curves. He said, but this is just a, it just happens to work this way. Then Einstein came along and said, well, by the way, the electromagnetic field might actually be discrete.
It might be made of photons. And then that explains how this all works. And that was, in 1905, that was how, kind of, that was how that piece of quantum mechanics got started. Kind of interesting, interesting piece of history. I didn't know until I was researching this recently. In 1904 and 1903, Einstein wrote three different papers.
And so, just sort of well-known physics history. In 1905, Einstein wrote these three papers. One introduced relativity theory, one explained Brownian motion, and one introduced basically photons. So, kind of, you know, kind of a big deal year for physics and for Einstein. But in the years before that, he'd written several papers, and what were they about?
They were about the second law of thermodynamics. And they were an attempt to prove the second law of thermodynamics, and they're nonsense. And so, I had no idea that he'd done this. - Interesting, me neither. - And in fact, what he did, those three papers in 1905, well, not so much the relativity paper, the one on Brownian motion, the one on photons, both of these were about the story of sort of making the world discreet.
And he got that idea from Boltzmann. But Boltzmann didn't think, you know, Boltzmann kind of died believing, you know, he said, as a quote, actually, you know, "In the end, things are gonna turn out to be discreet, "and I'm gonna write down what I have to say about this "because, you know, eventually this stuff "will be rediscovered and I want to leave, you know, "what I can about how things are gonna be discreet." But, you know, I think he has some quote about how, you know, one person can't stand against the tide of history in saying that, you know, matter is discreet.
- Oh, so he stuck by his guns in terms of matter is discreet. - Yes, he did. And the, you know, what's interesting about this is, at the time, everybody, including Einstein, kind of assumed that space was probably gonna end up being discreet too. But that didn't work out technically because it wasn't consistent with relativity theory, or it didn't seem to be.
And so then in the history of physics, even though people had determined that matter was discreet, the electromagnetic field was discreet, space was a holdout of not being discreet. And in fact, Einstein, 1916, has this nice letter he wrote, where he says, "In the end, it will turn out "space is discreet, but we don't have "the mathematical tools necessary "to figure out how that works yet." And so, you know, I think it's kind of cool that 100 years later we do.
- Yes, for you, you're pretty sure that at every layer of reality, it's discreet. - Right, and that space is discreet, and that the, I mean, and in fact, one of the things I realized recently is this kind of theory of heat, that the, you know, that heat is really this continuous fluid, it's kind of like, the caloric theory of heat, which turns out to be completely wrong, because actually, heat is the motion of discrete molecules.
Unless you know there are discrete molecules, it's hard to understand what heat could possibly be. Well, you know, I think space is discreet, and the question is kind of what's the analog of the mistake that was made with caloric in the case of space? And so my current guess is that dark matter is, as I've, my little sort of aphorism of the last few months has been, you know, dark matter is the caloric of our time.
That is, it will turn out that dark matter is a feature of space, and it is not a bunch of particles. You know, at the time when people were talking about heat, they knew about fluids, and they said, "Well, heat must just be another kind of fluid," 'cause that's what they knew about.
But now people know about particles, and so they say, "Well, what's dark matter?" It's not, it just must be particles. - So what could dark matter be as a feature of space? - Oh, I don't know yet. I mean, I think the thing I'm really, one of the things I'm hoping to be able to do is to find the analog of Brownian motion in space.
So in other words, Brownian motion was seeing down to the level of an effect from individual molecules. And so in the case of space, you know, most of the things, the things we see about space so far, just everything seems continuous. Brownian motion had been discovered in the 1830s, and it was only identified what it was the result of by Smoluchowski and Einstein at the beginning of the 20th century.
And, you know, dark matter was discovered, that phenomenon was discovered 100 years ago. You know, the rotation curves of galaxies don't follow the luminous matter. That was discovered 100 years ago. And I think, you know, I wouldn't be surprised if there isn't an effect that we already know about that is kind of the analog of Brownian motion that reveals the discreteness of space.
And in fact, we're beginning to have some guesses. We have some evidence that black hole mergers work differently when there's discrete space. And there may be things that you can see in gravitational wave signatures and things associated with the discreteness of space. But this is kind of, for me, it's kind of interesting to see this sort of recapitulation of the history of physics, where people, you know, vehemently say, you know, matter is continuous.
Electromagnetic field is continuous. And it turns out it isn't true. And then they say space is continuous. But so, you know, entropy is the number of states of the system consistent with some constraint. - Yes. - And the thing is that if you have, if you know in great detail the position of every molecule in the gas, the entropy is always zero, because there's only one possible state.
The configuration of molecules in the gas, the molecules bounce around, they have a certain rule for bouncing around. There's just one state of the gas, evolves to one state of the gas and so on. But it's only if you don't know in detail where all the molecules are, that you can say, well, the entropy increases because the things we do know about the molecules, there are more possible microscopic states of the system consistent with what we do know about where the molecules are.
And so the question of whether, so people, this sort of paradox in a sense of, oh, if we knew where all the molecules were, the entropy wouldn't increase. There was this idea introduced by Gibbs in the early 20th century, well, actually the very beginning of the 20th century, as a physics professor, an American physics professor, was sort of the first distinguished American physics professor at Yale.
And he introduced this idea of coarse graining. This idea that, well, you know, these molecules have a detailed way they're bouncing around, but we can only observe a coarse grained version of that. But the confusion has been, nobody knew what a valid coarse graining would be. So nobody knew that whether you could have this coarse graining that very carefully was sculpted in just such a way that it would notice that the particular configurations that you could get from the simple initial condition, you know, they fit into this coarse graining and the coarse graining very carefully observes that.
Why can't you do that kind of very detailed, precise coarse graining? The answer is because if you are a computationally bounded observer and the underlying dynamics is computationally irreducible, that's what defines possible coarse grainings is what a computationally bounded observer can do. And it's the fact that a computationally bounded observer is forced to look only at this kind of coarse grained version of what the system is doing.
That's why, and because what's going on underneath is it's kind of filling out this, the different possible, you're ending up with something where the sort of underlying computational irreducibility is, if all you can see is what the coarse grained result is with a sort of computationally bounded observation, then inevitably there are many possible underlying configurations that are consistent with that.
- Just to clarify, basically any observer that exists inside the universe is going to be computationally bounded. - No, any observer like us. I don't know, I can't imagine-- - When you say like us, what do you mean like us? - Well, humans with finite minds. - You're including the tools of science.
- Yeah, yeah. I mean, and as we have more precise, and by the way, there are little sort of microscopic violations of the second law of thermodynamics that you can start to have when you have more precise measurements of where precisely molecules are. But for a large scale, when you have enough molecules, we don't have, we're not tracing all those molecules and we just don't have the computational resources to do that, and it wouldn't be, I think to imagine what an observer who is not computationally bounded would be like, it's an interesting thing because, okay, so what does computational boundedness mean?
Among other things, it means we conclude that definite things happen. We go, we take all this complexity of the world and we make a decision, we're gonna turn left or turn right. And that is kind of reducing all this kind of detail into we're observing it, we're sort of crushing it down to this one thing.
And that, if we didn't do that, we wouldn't have all this sort of symbolic structure that we build up that lets us think things through with our finite minds. We'd be instead, we'd be just, we'd be sort of one with the universe. - Yeah, so content to not simplify.
- Yes, if we didn't simplify, then we wouldn't be like us. We would be like the universe, like the intrinsic universe, but not having experiences like the experiences we have where we, for example, conclude that definite things happen. We sort of have this notion of being able to make sort of narrative statements.
- Yeah, I wonder if it's just like you imagined as a thought experiment, what it's like to be a computer. I wonder if it's possible to try to begin to imagine what it's like to be an unbounded computational observer. - Well, okay, so here's how that, I think, plays out.
- Vibrations, yeah. - So, I mean, in this, we talk about this Rouliad, this space of all possible computations. And this idea of being at a certain place in the Rouliad, which corresponds to sort of a certain way of, a certain set of computations that you are representing things in terms of.
Okay, so as you expand out in the Rouliad, as you kind of encompass more possible views of the universe, as you encompass more possible kinds of computations that you can do, eventually, you might say, "That's a real win. "We're colonizing the Rouliad. "We're building out more paradigms "about how to think about things." And eventually, you might say, "We won all the way.
"We managed to colonize the whole Rouliad." Okay, here's the problem with that. The problem is that the notion of existence, coherent existence, requires some kind of specialization. By the time you are the whole Rouliad, by the time you cover the whole Rouliad, in no useful sense do you coherently exist.
So in other words, in-- - Oh, interesting. - The notion of existence, the notion of what we think of as definite existence, requires this kind of specialization, requires this kind of idea that we are not all possible things. We are a particular set of things. And that's kind of how we, that's kind of what makes us have a coherent existence.
If we were spread throughout the Rouliad, we would not, there would be no coherence to the way that we work. We would work in all possible ways. And that wouldn't be kind of a notion of identity. We wouldn't have this notion of kind of coherent identity. - I am geographically located somewhere exactly, precisely in the Rouliad, therefore I am.
- Yes. - Is the Descartes kind of-- - Yeah, yeah, right. Well, you're in a certain place in physical space, you're in a certain place in Roulial space. And if you are sufficiently spread out, you are no longer coherent. And you no longer have, I mean, in our perception of what it means to exist and to have experience, it doesn't happen that way.
- So therefore, to exist means to be computationally bounded. - I think so. To exist in the way that we think of ourselves as existing. Yes. - The very act of existence is like operating in this place that's computationally irreducible. So there's this giant mess of things going on that you can't possibly predict.
But nevertheless, because of your limitations, you have an imperative of like, what is it? An imperative or a skill set to simplify? Or an ignorance, a sufficient-- - Okay, so the thing which is not obvious is that you are taking a slice of all this complexity. Just like we have all of these molecules bouncing around in the room, but all we notice is the kind of the flow of the air or the pressure of the air.
We're just noticing these particular things. And the big interesting thing is that there are rules, there are laws that govern those big things we observe. So it's not obvious. - It's amazing, 'cause it doesn't feel like it's a slice. - Yeah, well, right. - It's not a slice. It's like an abstraction.
- Yes, but I mean, the fact that the gas laws work, that we can describe pressure, volume, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. We don't have to go down to the level of talking about individual molecules. That is a non-trivial fact. And here's the thing that I sort of exciting thing as far as I'm concerned.
The fact that there are certain aspects of the universe. So we think space is made ultimately these atoms of space and these hypergraphs and so on. And we think that, but we nevertheless perceive the universe at a large scale to be like continuous space and so on. We in quantum mechanics, we think that there are these many threads of time, these many threads of history, yet we kind of span.
So in quantum mechanics and our models of physics, there are these, time is not a single thread. Time breaks into many threads. They branch, they merge. But we are part of that branching, merging universe. And so our brains are also branching and merging. And so when we perceive the universe, we are branching brains perceiving a branching universe.
And so the fact that the claim that we believe that we are persistent in time, we have this single thread of experience. That's the statement that somehow we managed to aggregate together those separate threads of time that are separated in the operation of, in the fundamental operation of the universe.
So just as in space, we're averaging over some big region of space and we're looking at many, many of the aggregate effects of many atoms of space. So similarly, in what we call branchial space, the space of these quantum branches, we are effectively averaging over many different branches of possible of histories of the universe.
And so in thermodynamics, we're averaging over many configurations of, many possible positions of molecules. So what we see here is, so the question is, when you do that averaging for space, what are the aggregate laws of space? When you do that averaging of a branchial space, what are the aggregate laws of branchial space?
When you do that averaging over the molecules and so on, what are the aggregate laws you get? And this is the thing that I think is just amazingly, amazingly neat. - That there are aggregate laws at all. - Well, yes, but the question is, what are those aggregate laws?
So the answer is for space, the aggregate laws are Einstein's equations for gravity, for the structure of space time. For branchial space, the aggregate laws are the laws of quantum mechanics. And for the case of molecules and things, the aggregate laws are basically the second law of thermodynamics. And so that's the, and the things that follow from the second law of thermodynamics.
And so what that means is that the three great theories of 20th century physics, which are basically general relativity, the theory of gravity, quantum mechanics, and statistical mechanics, which is what kind of grows out of the second law of thermodynamics. All three of the great theories of 20th century physics are the result of this interplay between computational irreducibility and the computational boundedness of observers.
And for me, this is really neat because it means that all three of these laws are derivable. So we used to think that, for example, Einstein's equations were just sort of a wheel in feature of our universe, that they could be, the universe might be that way, it might not be that way.
Quantum mechanics is just like, well, it just happens to be that way. And the second law, people kind of thought, well, maybe it is derivable, okay? What turns out to be the case is that all three of the fundamental principles of physics are derivable, but they're not derivable just from mathematics.
They require, or just from some kind of logical computation, they require one more thing. They require that the observer, that the thing that is sampling the way the universe works is an observer who has these characteristics of computational boundedness of belief and persistence in time. And so that means that it is the nature of the observer, the rough nature of the observer, not the details of, oh, we got two eyes and we observe photons of this frequency and so on, but the kind of the very coarse features of the observer then imply these very precise facts about physics.
And I think it's amazing. - So if we just look at the actual experience of the observer that we experience this reality, it seems real to us. And you're saying because of our bounded nature, it's actually all an illusion. It's a simplification. - Yeah, it's a simplification. Right, what's-- - So you don't think a simplification is an illusion?
- No, I mean, it's, well, I don't know. I mean, what's underneath-- - Is it real? - Okay, that's an interesting question. What's real? And that relates to the whole question of why does the universe exist? And what is the difference between reality and a mere representation of what's going on?
- Yes, we experience the representation. - Yes, but the question of, so one question is, why is there a thing which we can experience that way? And the answer is because this Rouliad object, which is this entangled limit of all possible computations, there is no choice about it. It has to exist.
It has to, there has to be such a thing. It is in the same sense that, you know, two plus two, if you define what two is and you plot pluses and so on, two plus two has to equal four. Similarly, this Rouliad, this limit of all possible computations, just has to be a thing that is, once you have the idea of computation, you inevitably have the Rouliad.
- You're gonna have to have a Rouliad, yeah. - Right, and what's important about it, there's just one of it. It's just this unique object. And that unique object necessarily exists. And then the question is, what, and then we are, once you know that we are sort of embedded in that and taking samples of it, that it's sort of inevitable that there is this thing that we can perceive that is, you know, our perception of kind of physical reality necessarily is that way, given that we are observers with the characteristics we have.
So in other words, the fact that, the fact that the universe exists is, it's actually, it's almost like, it's, you know, to think about it almost theologically, so to speak. And I've really, it's funny because a lot of the questions about the existence of the universe and so on, they transcend what kind of the science of the last few hundred years has really been concerned with.
The science of the last few hundred years hasn't thought it could talk about questions like that. And, but I think it's kind of, and so a lot of the kind of arguments of, you know, does God exist? You know, is it obvious that, I think it, in some sense, in some representation, it's sort of more obvious that, that something sort of bigger than us exists than that we exist.
And we are, you know, our existence and as observers the way we are is sort of a contingent thing about the universe. And it's more inevitable that the whole universe, kind of the whole set of all possibilities exists. But this question about, you know, is it real or is it an illusion?
You know, all we know is our experience. And so the fact that, well, our experience is this absolutely microscopic piece of sample of the Roulade. And we're, and you know, there's this point about, you know, we might sample more and more of the Roulade. We might learn more and more about, we might learn, you know, like different areas of physics, like quantum mechanics, for example.
The fact that it was discovered, I think is closely related to the fact that electronic amplifiers were invented that allowed you to take a small effect and amplify it up, which hadn't been possible before. You know, microscopes had been invented that magnify things and so on. But the, you know, having a very small effect and being able to magnify it was sort of a new thing that allowed one to see a different sort of aspect of the universe and let one discover this kind of thing.
So, you know, we can expect that in the Roulade, there are an infinite collection of new things we can discover. There's in fact computational irreducibility kind of guarantees that there will be an infinite collection of kind of, you know, pockets of reducibility that can be discovered. - Boy, would it be fun to take a walk down the Roulade and see what kind of stuff we find there.
You write about alien intelligences. - Yes. - It's these worlds of computation. - Yes, well, quite, but the problem with these worlds is that- - We can't talk to them. - Yes. And, you know, the thing is, what I've kind of spent a lot of time doing is just studying computational systems, seeing what they do, what I now call Rouleology, kind of just the study of rules and what they do.
You know, you can kind of easily jump somewhere else in the Roulade and start seeing what do these rules do. And what you, as they just, they do what they do, and there's no human connection, so to speak. - Do you think, you know, some people are able to communicate with animals?
Do you think you can become a whisperer of these- - Oh, I've been trying. That's what I've spent some part of my life doing. - Have you heard? And are you at the risk of losing your mind? - Sort of my favorite science discovery is this fact that these very simple programs can produce very complicated behavior.
- Yeah, it's beautiful. - And that fact is kind of, in a sense, a whispering of something out in the computational universe that we didn't really know was there before. I mean, it's, you know, it's like, you know, back in the 1980s, I was doing a bunch of work with some very, very good mathematicians, and they were like trying to pick away, you know, can we figure out what's going on in these computational systems?
And they basically said, look, the math we have just doesn't get anywhere with this, we're stuck. There's nothing to say, we have nothing to say. And, you know, in a sense, perhaps my main achievement at that time was to realize that the very fact that the good mathematicians had nothing to say was itself a very interesting thing.
That was kind of a sort of, in some sense, a whispering of a different part of the Roulade that one hadn't, you know, one wasn't, was not accessible from what we knew in mathematics and so on. - Does it make you sad that you're exploring some of these gigantic ideas, and it feels like we're on the verge of breaking through to some very interesting discoveries, and yet you're just a finite being that's going to die way too soon, and that scan of your brain, your full body, kind of shows that you're-- - Yeah, it's just a bunch of meat.
- It's just a bunch of meat. Yeah, does that make you a little sad? - Kind of a shame. I mean, I'd kind of like to see how all this stuff works out, but I think the thing to realize, you know, it's an interesting sort of thought experiment. You know, you say, okay, you know, let's assume we can get cryonics to work, and one day it will.
That will be one of these things that's kind of like chat GPT. One day somebody will figure out, you know, how to get water from zero degrees centigrade down to, you know, minus 44 or something without it expanding, and, you know, cryonics will be solved, and you'll be able to, like, just, you know, put a pause in, so to speak, and, you know, kind of reappear 100 years later or something, and the thing, though, that I've kind of increasingly realized is that, in a sense, this whole question of kind of the sort of one is embedded in a certain moment in time, and, you know, kind of the things we care about now, the things I care about now, for example, had I lived, you know, 500 years ago, many of the things I care about now, it's like, that's totally bizarre.
I mean, nobody would care about that. It's not even the thing one thinks about. In the future, the things that most people will think about, you know, one will be a strange relic of thinking about, you know, the kind of, you know, it might be, one might have been a theologian thinking about, you know, how many angels fit on the head of a pin or something, and that might have been the, you know, the big intellectual thing.
So I think it's a, but yeah, it's a, you know, it's one of these things where, particularly, you know, I've had the, I don't know, good or bad fortune, I'm not sure, I think it's a mixed thing, that I've, you know, I've invented a bunch of things, which I kind of can, I think, see well enough what's gonna happen that, you know, in 50 years, 100 years, whatever, assuming the world doesn't exterminate itself, so to speak, you know, these are things that will be sort of centrally important to what's going on, and it's kind of both, it's both a good thing and a bad thing in terms of the passage of one's life.
I mean, it's kind of like, if everything I'd figured out was like, okay, I figured it out when I was 25 years old, and everybody says it's great, and we're done, and it's like, okay, but I'm gonna live another, how many years, and that's kind of, it's all downhill from there.
In a sense, it's better, in some sense, to be able to, you know, there's, it sort of keeps things interesting that, you know, I can see, you know, a lot of these things, I mean, it's kind of, I didn't expect, you know, chat GPT, I didn't expect the kind of, the sort of opening up of this idea of computation and computational language that's been made possible by this.
I didn't expect that. This is ahead of schedule, so to speak. You know, even though the sort of, the big kind of flowering of that stuff, I'd sort of been assuming was another 50 years away. So if it turns out it's a lot less time, that's pretty cool, because, you know, I'll hopefully get to see it, so to speak, rather than then.
- Well, I think I speak for a very, very large number of people in saying that I hope you stick around for a long time to come. You've had so many interesting ideas. You've created so many interesting systems over the years, and I can see, now that GPT and language models broke open the world even more, I can't wait to see you at the forefront of this development, what you do.
And yeah, I've been a fan of yours, like I've told you many, many times since the very beginning. I'm deeply grateful that you wrote a new kind of science, that you explored this mystery of cellular automata, and inspired this one little kid in me to pursue artificial intelligence in all this beautiful world, so Steven, thank you so much, it's a huge honor to talk to you, to just be able to pick your mind and to explore all these ideas with you, and please keep going, and I can't wait to see what you come up with next.
And thank you for talking today. - Thanks. - We went past midnight, we only did four and a half hours. I mean, we could probably go for four more, but we'll save that 'til next time. This is round number four, we'll, I'm sure, talk many more times. Thank you so much.
- My pleasure. - Thanks for listening to this conversation with Steven Wolfram. To support this podcast, please check out our sponsors in the description. And now, let me leave you with some words from George Cantor. "The essence of mathematics lies in its freedom." Thank you for listening, and hope to see you next time.
(upbeat music) (upbeat music)