Back to Index

Michael Kearns: Algorithmic Fairness, Privacy & Ethics | Lex Fridman Podcast #50


Chapters

0:0
47:31 Social Media Platforms
67:6 What Is Differential Privacy
67:24 Anonymization of Data
67:57 Anonymization
71:58 Differential Privacy
75:21 Mechanism of Differential Privacy
88:0 Game Theory
88:24 Algorithmic Game Theory
88:46 Prisoner's Dilemma
97:1 Algorithmic Trading

Transcript

The following is a conversation with Michael Kearns. He's a professor at the University of Pennsylvania and a co-author of the new book, Ethical Algorithm, that is the focus of much of this conversation. It includes algorithmic fairness, bias, privacy, and ethics in general. But that is just one of many fields that Michael is a world-class researcher in, some of which we touch on quickly, including learning theory or the theoretical foundation of machine learning, game theory, quantitative finance, computational social science, and much more.

But on a personal note, when I was an undergrad, early on, I worked with Michael on an algorithmic trading project and competition that he led. That's when I first fell in love with algorithmic game theory. While most of my research life has been in machine learning and human-robot interaction, the systematic way that game theory reveals the beautiful structure in our competitive and cooperating world of humans has been a continued inspiration to me.

So for that and other things, I'm deeply thankful to Michael and really enjoyed having this conversation again in person after so many years. This is the Artificial Intelligence Podcast. If you enjoy it, subscribe on YouTube, give it five stars on Apple Podcasts, support on Patreon, or simply connect with me on Twitter @LexFriedman, spelled F-R-I-D-M-A-N.

This episode is supported by an amazing podcast called Pessimists Archive. Jason, the host of the show, reached out to me looking to support this podcast, and so I listened to it to check it out. And by listened, I mean I went through it Netflix binge-style at least five episodes in a row.

It's not one of my favorite podcasts, and I think it should be one of the top podcasts in the world, frankly. It's a history show about why people resist new things. Each episode looks at a moment in history when something new was introduced, something that today we think of as commonplace, like recorded music, umbrellas, bicycles, cars, chess, coffee, the elevator, and the show explores why it freaked everyone out.

The latest episode on mirrors and vanity still stays with me as I think about vanity in the modern day of the Twitter world. That's the fascinating thing about this show, is that stuff that happened long ago, especially in terms of our fear of new things, repeats itself in the modern day and so has many lessons for us to think about in terms of human psychology and the role of technology in our society.

Anyway, you should subscribe and listen to Pessimists Archive. I highly recommend it. And now, here's my conversation with Michael Kearns. You mentioned reading Fear and Loathing in Las Vegas in high school and having a more or a bit more of a literary mind. So, what books, non-technical, non-computer science, would you say had the biggest impact on your life, either intellectually or emotionally?

You've dug deep into my history, I see. Went deep. Yeah, I think, well, my favorite novel is Infinite Jest by David Foster Wallace, which actually, coincidentally, much of it takes place in the halls of buildings right around us here at MIT. So, that certainly had a big influence on me.

And as you noticed, like when I was in high school, I actually even started college as an English major. So, I was very influenced by sort of that genre of journalism at the time and thought I wanted to be a writer and then realized that an English major teaches you to read, but it doesn't teach you how to write.

And then I became interested in math and computer science instead. Well, in your new book, Ethical Algorithm, you kind of sneak up from an algorithmic perspective on these deep, profound philosophical questions of fairness, of privacy. In thinking about these topics, how often do you return to that literary mind that you had?

Yeah, I'd like to claim there was a deeper connection, but I think both Aaron and I kind of came at these topics first and foremost from a technical angle. I mean, I kind of consider myself primarily and originally a machine learning researcher. And I think as we just watched, like the rest of the society, the field technically advance, and then quickly on the heels of that, kind of the buzzkill of all of the antisocial behavior by algorithms, just kind of realized there was an opportunity for us to do something about it from a research perspective.

More to the point of your question, I mean, I do have an uncle who is literally a moral philosopher. And so in the early days of our technical work on fairness topics, I would occasionally run ideas behind him. So I mean, I remember an early email I sent to him in which I said like, "Oh, here's a specific definition of algorithmic fairness that we think is some sort of variant of Rawlsian fairness.

What do you think?" And I thought I was asking a yes or no question, and I got back to a kind of classical philosopher's response. "Well, it depends. If you look at it this way, then you might conclude this." And that's when I realized that there was a real kind of rift between the ways philosophers and others had thought about things like fairness from sort of a humanitarian perspective and the way that you needed to think about it as a computer scientist if you were going to kind of implement actual algorithmic solutions.

- But I would say the algorithmic solutions take care of some of the low-hanging fruit. Sort of the problem is a lot of algorithms, when they don't consider fairness, they are just terribly unfair. And when they don't consider privacy, they're terribly, they violate privacy. Sort of the algorithmic approach fixes big problems.

But there is still, when you start pushing into the gray area, that's when you start getting into this philosophy of what it means to be fair, starting from Plato, what is justice kind of questions. - Yeah, I think that's right. And I mean, I would even not go as far as you went to say that sort of the algorithmic work in these areas is solving like the biggest problems.

And we discuss in the book the fact that really we are, there's a sense in which we're kind of looking where the light is in that, for example, if police are racist in who they decide to stop and frisk, and that goes into the data, there's sort of no undoing that downstream by kind of clever algorithmic methods.

And I think, especially in fairness, I mean, I think less so in privacy, where we feel like the community kind of really has settled on the right definition, which is differential privacy. If you just look at the algorithmic fairness literature already, you can see it's gonna be much more of a mess.

And you've got these theorems saying, here are three entirely reasonable, desirable notions of fairness. And here's a proof that you cannot simultaneously have all three of them. So I think we know that algorithmic fairness compared to algorithmic privacy is gonna be kind of a harder problem. And it will have to revisit, I think, things that have been thought about by many generations of scholars before us.

So it's very early days for fairness, I think. - So before we get into the details of differential privacy and on the fairness side, let me linger on the philosophy a bit. Do you think most people are fundamentally good? Or do most of us have both the capacity for good and evil within us?

- I mean, I'm an optimist. I tend to think that most people are good and want to do right. And that deviations from that are kind of usually due to circumstance, not due to people being bad at heart. - With people with power, are people at the heads of governments, people at the heads of companies, people at the heads of maybe, so financial power markets.

Do you think the distribution there is also most people are good and have good intent? - Yeah, I do. I mean, my statement wasn't qualified to people not in positions of power. I mean, I think what happens in a lot of the cliche about absolute power corrupts absolutely. I mean, I think even short of that, having spent a lot of time on Wall Street and also in arenas very, very different from Wall Street, like academia, one of the things I think I've benefited from by moving between two very different worlds is you become aware that these worlds kind of develop their own social norms and they develop their own rationales for behavior, for instance, that might look unusual to outsiders.

But when you're in that world, it doesn't feel unusual at all. And I think this is true of a lot of professional cultures, for instance. And so then your maybe slippery slope is too strong of a word, but you're in some world where you're mainly around other people with the same kind of viewpoints and training and worldview as you.

And I think that's more of a source of abuses of power than sort of there being good people and evil people and that somehow the evil people are the ones that somehow rise to power. - That's really interesting. So it's within the social norms constructed by that particular group of people, you're all trying to do good, but because it's a group, you might drift into something that for the broader population it does not align with the values of society.

That's the worry. - Yeah, I mean, or not that you drift, but even the things that don't make sense to the outside world don't seem unusual to you. So it's not sort of like a good or a bad thing, but, you know, like, so for instance, you know, in the world of finance, right, there's a lot of complicated types of activity that if you are not immersed in that world, you cannot see why the purpose of that, you know, that activity exists at all.

It just seems like, you know, completely useless and people just like, you know, pushing money around. And when you're in that world, right, and you learn more, your view does become more nuanced, right? You realize, okay, there is actually a function to this activity. And in some cases you would conclude that actually if magically we could eradicate this activity tomorrow, it would come back because it actually is like serving some useful purpose.

It's just a useful purpose that's very difficult for outsiders to see. And so I think, you know, lots of professional work environments or cultures, as I might put it, kind of have these social norms that, you know, don't make sense to the outside world. Academia is the same, right?

I mean, lots of people look at academia and say, you know, what the hell are all of you people doing? Why are you paid so much in some cases at taxpayer expenses to do, you know, to publish papers that nobody reads? You know, but when you're in that world, you come to see the value for it.

And, but even though you might not be able to explain it to, you know, the person in the street. Right. And in the case of the financial sector, tools like credit might not make sense to people. Like it's a good example of something that does seem to pop up and be useful, or just the power of markets and just in general capitalism.

Yeah. And finance, I think the primary example I would give is leverage, right? So being allowed to borrow, to sort of use 10 times as much money as you've actually borrowed, right? So that's an example of something that before I had any experience in financial markets, I might've looked at and said, well, what is the purpose of that?

That just seems very dangerous. And it is dangerous and it has proven dangerous. But, you know, if the fact of the matter is that, you know, sort of on some particular timescale, you are holding positions that are, you know, very unlikely to, you know, lose, you know, their, you know, like your value at risk or variances like one or 5%, then it kind of makes sense that you would be allowed to use a little bit more than you have, because you have, you know, some confidence that you're not going to lose it all in a single day.

Now, of course, when that happens, we've seen what happens, you know, not too long ago. But, you know, but the idea that it serves no useful economic purpose under any circumstances is definitely not true. We'll return to the other side of the coast, Silicon Valley, and the problems there as we talk about privacy, as we talk about fairness.

At the high level, and I'll ask some sort of basic questions with the hope to get at the fundamental nature of reality. But from a very high level, what is an ethical algorithm? So I can say that an algorithm has a running time of using big O notation and log N.

I can say that a machine learning algorithm classified cat versus dog with 97% accuracy. Do you think there will one day be a way to measure sort of in the same compelling way as the big O notation of this algorithm is 97% ethical? First of all, let me riff for a second on your specific N log N example.

So because early in the book, when we're just kind of trying to describe algorithms, period, we say like, okay, what's an example of an algorithm or an algorithmic problem? First of all, it's sorting, right? You have a bunch of index cards with numbers on them and you want to sort them.

And we describe an algorithm that sweeps all the way through, finds the smallest number, puts it at the front, then sweeps through again, finds the second smallest number. So we make the point that this is an algorithm, and it's also a bad algorithm in the sense that it's quadratic rather than N log N, which we know is kind of optimal for sorting.

And we make the point that sort of like, so even within the confines of a very precisely specified problem, there might be many, many different algorithms for the same problem with different properties. Like some might be faster in terms of running time, some might use less memory, some might have better distributed implementations.

And so the point is, is that already we're used to, you know, in computer science, thinking about trade-offs between different types of quantities and resources, and there being, you know, better and worse algorithms. And our book is about that part of algorithmic ethics that we know how to kind of put on that same kind of quantitative footing right now.

So, you know, just to say something that our book is not about, our book is not about kind of broad, fuzzy notions of fairness. It's about very specific notions of fairness. There's more than one of them. There are tensions between them, right? But if you pick one of them, you can do something akin to saying that this algorithm is 97% ethical.

You can say, for instance, the, you know, for this lending model, the false rejection rate on black people and white people is within 3%, right? So we might call that a 97% ethical algorithm, and a 100% ethical algorithm would mean that that difference is 0%. >> In that case, fairness is specified when two groups, however they're defined, are given to you.

>> That's right. >> So the, and then you can sort of mathematically start describing the algorithm. But nevertheless, the part where the two groups are given to you, unlike running time, you know, we don't in computer science talk about how fast an algorithm feels like when it runs. >> True.

>> We measure it, and ethical starts getting into feelings. So for example, an algorithm runs, you know, if it runs in the background, it doesn't disturb the performance of my system, it'll feel nice, I'll be okay with it. But if it overloads the system, it'll feel unpleasant. So in that same way, ethics, there's a feeling of how socially acceptable it is, how does it represent the moral standards of our society today?

So in that sense, and sorry to linger on that first high-level philosophical question, is do you have a sense we'll be able to measure how ethical an algorithm is? >> First of all, I didn't, certainly didn't mean to give the impression that you can kind of measure, you know, memory speed trade-offs, you know, and that there's a complete, you know, mapping from that on to kind of fairness, for instance, or ethics and accuracy, for example.

In the type of fairness definitions that are largely the objects of study today and starting to be deployed, you as the user of the definitions, you need to make some hard decisions before you even get to the point of designing fair algorithms. One of them, for instance, is deciding who it is that you're worried about protecting, who you're worried about being harmed by, for instance, some notion of discrimination or unfairness.

And then you need to also decide what constitutes harm. So for instance, in a lending application, maybe you decide that, you know, falsely rejecting a creditworthy individual, you know, sort of a false negative, is the real harm, and that false positives, i.e. people that are not creditworthy or are not going to repay your loan, that get a loan, you might think of them as lucky.

And so that's not a harm, although it's not clear that if you don't have the means to repay a loan, that being given a loan is not also a harm. So, you know, the literature is sort of so far quite limited in that you sort of need to say, who do you want to protect and what would constitute harm to that group?

And when you ask questions like, will algorithms feel ethical, one way in which they won't under the definitions that I'm describing is if, you know, if you are an individual who is falsely denied a loan, incorrectly denied a loan, all of these definitions basically say like, well, you know, your compensation is the knowledge that we are also falsely denying loans to other people, you know, in other groups at the same rate that we're doing it to you.

And, you know, and so there is actually this interesting, even technical tension in the field right now between these sort of group notions of fairness and notions of fairness that might actually feel like real fairness to individuals, right? They might really feel like their particular interests are being protected or thought about by the algorithm rather than just, you know, the groups that they happen to be members of.

- Is there parallels to the big O notation of worst case analysis? So is it important to, looking at the worst violation of fairness for an individual, is it important to minimize that one individual? So like worst case analysis, is that something you think about or? - I mean, I think we're not even at the point where we can sensibly think about that.

So first of all, you know, we're talking here both about fairness applied at the group level, which is a relatively weak thing, but it's better than nothing. And also the more ambitious thing of trying to give some individual promises. But even that doesn't incorporate, I think, something that you're hinting at here is what I might have called subjective fairness, right?

So a lot of the definitions, I mean, all of the definitions in the algorithmic fairness literature are what I would kind of call received wisdom definitions. It's sort of, you know, somebody like me sits around and thinks like, okay, you know, I think here's a technical definition of fairness that I think people should want, or that they should, you know, think of as some notion of fairness, maybe not the only one, maybe not the best one, maybe not the last one.

But we really actually don't know from a subjective standpoint, like what people really think is fair. There's, you know, we just started doing a little bit of work in our group at actually doing kind of human subject experiments in which we, you know, ask people about, you know, we ask them questions about fairness, we survey them, we, you know, we show them pairs of individuals in, let's say, a criminal recidivism prediction setting, and we ask them, do you think these two individuals should be treated the same as a matter of fairness?

And to my knowledge, there's not a large literature in which ordinary people are asked about, you know, they have sort of notions of their subjective fairness elicited from them. It's mainly, you know, kind of scholars who think about fairness, you know, kind of making up their own definitions. And I think this needs to change actually for many social norms, not just for fairness, right?

So there's a lot of, you know, discussion these days in the AI community about interpretable AI or understandable AI. And as far as I can tell, everybody agrees that deep learning, or at least the outputs of deep learning, are not very understandable. And people might agree that sparse linear models with integer coefficients are more understandable.

But nobody's really asked people, you know, there's very little literature on, you know, sort of showing people models and asking them, do they understand what the model is doing? And I think that in all these topics, as these fields mature, we need to start doing more behavioral work. Yeah, which is, so one of my deep passions is psychology.

And I always thought computer scientists will be the best future psychologists, in a sense that data is, especially in this modern world, the data is a really powerful way to understand and study human behavior. And you've explored that with your game theory side of work as well. Yeah, I'd like to think that what you say is true about computer scientists and psychology, from my own limited wandering into human subject experiments, we have a great deal to learn.

Not just computer science, but AI and machine learning more specifically, I kind of think of as imperialist research communities in that, you know, kind of like physicists in an earlier generation, computer scientists kind of don't think of any scientific topic as off limits to them, they will like freely wander into areas that others have been thinking about for decades or longer.

And, you know, we usually tend to embarrass ourselves in those efforts for some amount of time. Like, you know, I think reinforcement learning is a good example, right? So a lot of the early work in reinforcement learning, I have complete sympathy for the control theorists that looked at this and said, like, okay, you are reinventing stuff that we've known since like the 40s, right?

But, you know, in my view, eventually, this sort of, you know, computer scientists have made significant contributions to that field, even though we kind of embarrassed ourselves for the first decade. So I think if computer scientists are going to start engaging in kind of psychology, human subjects, type of research, we should expect to be embarrassing ourselves for a good 10 years or so, and then hope that it turns out as well as, you know, some other areas that we've waded into.

>> So you've kind of mentioned this, just to linger on the idea of an ethical algorithm, of idea of groups, sort of group thinking and individual thinking. And we're struggling that, one of the amazing things about algorithms and your book and just this field of study is it gets us to ask, like, forcing machines, converting these ideas into algorithms is forcing us to ask questions of ourselves as a human civilization.

So there's a lot of people now in public discourse doing sort of group thinking, thinking like there's particular sets of groups that we don't want to discriminate against and so on. And then there's individuals, sort of in the individual life stories, the struggles they went through and so on.

Now, like in philosophy, it's easier to do group thinking because you don't, you know, it's very hard to think about individuals, there's so much variability. But with data, you can start to actually say, you know, what group thinking is too crude? You're actually doing more discrimination by thinking in terms of groups and individuals.

Can you linger on that kind of idea of group versus individual and ethics? And is it good to continue thinking in terms of groups in algorithms? - So let me start by answering a very good high level question with a slightly narrow technical response, which is these group definitions of fairness, like here's a few groups, like different racial groups, maybe gender groups, maybe age, what have you.

And let's make sure that, you know, for none of these groups, do we, you know, have a false negative rate, which is much higher than any other one of these groups, okay? So these are kind of classic group aggregate notions of fairness. And, you know, but at the end of the day, an individual you can think of as a combination of all of their attributes, right?

They're a member of a racial group, they have a gender, they have an age, you know, and many other, you know, demographic properties that are not biological, but that, you know, are still, you know, very strong determinants of outcome and personality and the like. So one, I think, useful spectrum is to sort of think about that array between the group and the specific individual, and to realize that in some ways, asking for fairness at the individual level is to sort of ask for group fairness simultaneously for all possible combinations of groups.

So in particular, you know, if I build a predictive model that meets some definition of fairness by race, by gender, by age, by what have you, marginally, to get slightly technical, sort of independently, I shouldn't expect that model to not discriminate against disabled Hispanic women over age 55, making less than $50,000 a year annually, even though I might have protected each one of those attributes marginally.

>> So the optimization, actually, that's a fascinating way to put it. So you're just optimizing, so one way to achieve the optimizing fairness for individuals is just to add more and more definitions of groups that each individual belongs to. >> So, you know, at the end of the day, we could think of all of ourselves as groups of size one, because eventually there's some attribute that separates you from me and everybody, from everybody else in the world, okay?

And so it is possible to put, you know, these incredibly coarse ways of thinking about fairness and these very, very individualistic, specific ways on a common scale. And, you know, one of the things we've worked on from a research perspective is, you know, so we sort of know how to, you know, in relative terms, we know how to provide fairness guarantees at the coarsest end of the scale.

We don't know how to provide kind of sensible, tractable, realistic fairness guarantees at the individual level, but maybe we could start creeping towards that by dealing with more, you know, refined subgroups. I mean, we gave a name to this phenomenon where, you know, you protect, you enforce some definition of fairness for a bunch of marginal attributes or features, but then you find yourself discriminating against a combination of them.

We call that fairness gerrymandering, because like political gerrymandering, you know, you're giving some guarantee at the aggregate level, but that when you kind of look in a more granular way at what's going on, you realize that you're achieving that aggregate guarantee by sort of favoring some groups and discriminating against other ones.

And so there are, you know, it's early days, but there are algorithmic approaches that let you start creep, creeping towards that, you know, individual end of the spectrum. Does there need to be human input in the form of weighing the value of the importance of each kind of group?

So for example, is it like, so gender, say, crudely speaking, male and female, and then different races, are we as humans supposed to put value on saying gender is 0.6 and race is 0.4 in terms of in the big optimization of achieving fairness? Is that kind of what humans- I mean, you know, I mean, of course, you know, I don't need to tell you that, of course, technically one could incorporate such weights if you wanted to into a definition of fairness.

You know, fairness is an interesting topic in that having worked in, in the book being about both fairness, privacy, and many other social norms, fairness, of course, is a much, much more loaded topic. So privacy, I mean, people want privacy, people don't like violations of privacy, violations of privacy cause damage, angst, and bad publicity for the companies that are victims of them.

But sort of everybody agrees more data privacy would be better than less data privacy. And you don't have these, somehow the discussions of fairness don't become politicized along other dimensions like race and about gender and, you know, whether we, and, you know, you quickly find yourselves kind of revisiting topics that have been kind of unresolved forever, like affirmative action, right?

Sort of, you know, like, why are you protecting, some people will say, why are you protecting this particular racial group? And, and others will say, well, we need to do that as a matter of, of retribution. Other people will say it's a matter of economic opportunity. And I don't know which of, you know, whether any of these are the right answers, but you sort of fairness is sort of special in that as soon as you start talking about it, you inevitably have to participate in debates about fair to whom, at what expense to who else.

I mean, even in criminal justice, right? You know, where people talk about fairness in criminal sentencing, or, you know, predicting failures to appear or making parole decisions or the like, they will, you know, they'll point out that, well, these definitions of fairness are all about fairness for the criminals.

And what about fairness for the victims, right? So when I basically say something like, well, the false incarceration rate for black people and white people needs to be roughly the same, you know, there's no mention of potential victims of criminals in such a fairness definition. And that's the realm of public discord.

I should actually recommend, I just listened to people listening, Intelligence Squares debates, US edition just had a debate. They have this structure where you have old Oxford style or whatever they're called, debates, and it was two versus two, and they talked about affirmative action. And it was incredibly interesting that it's still, there's really good points on every side of this issue, which is fascinating to listen to.

Yeah, yeah, I agree. And so it's interesting to be a researcher trying to do, for the most part, technical algorithmic work. But Aaron and I both quickly learned you cannot do that and then go out and talk about it and expect people to take it seriously if you're unwilling to engage in these broader debates that are entirely extra algorithmic, right?

They're not about, you know, algorithms and making algorithms better. They're sort of, you know, as you said, sort of like, what should society be protecting in the first place? When you discuss the fairness, an algorithm that achieves fairness, whether in the constraints and the objective function, there's an immediate kind of analysis you can perform, which is saying, if you care about fairness in gender, this is the amount that you have to pay for in terms of the performance of the system.

Is there a role for statements like that in a table in a paper, or do you want to really not touch that? No, we want to touch that and we do touch it. So, I mean, just again to make sure I'm not promising your viewers more than we know how to provide.

But if you pick a definition of fairness, like I'm worried about gender discrimination, and you pick a notion of harm, like false rejection for a loan, for example, and you give me a model, I can definitely, first of all, go audit that model. It's easy for me to go, you know, from data to kind of say like, okay, your false rejection rate on women is this much higher than it is on men, okay?

But, you know, once you also put the fairness into your objective function, I mean, I think the table that you're talking about is, you know, what we would call the Pareto curve, right? You can literally trace out, and we give examples of such plots on real data sets in the book, you have two axes.

On the x-axis is your error, on the y-axis is unfairness by whatever, you know, if it's like the disparity between false rejection rates between two groups. And, you know, your algorithm now has a knob that basically says, how strongly do I want to enforce fairness? And the less unfair, you know, if the two axes are error and unfairness, we'd like to be at zero, zero.

We'd like zero error and zero unfairness simultaneously. Anybody who works in machine learning knows that you're generally not going to get to zero error period without any fairness constraint whatsoever, so that's not going to happen. But in general, you know, you'll get this, you'll get some kind of convex curve that specifies the numerical tradeoff you face, you know, if I want to go from 17% error down to 16% error, what will be the increase in unfairness that I experience as a result of that?

And so this curve kind of specifies the, you know, kind of undominated models. Models that are off that curve are, you know, can be strictly improved in one or both dimensions. You can, you know, either make the error better or the unfairness better or both. And I think our view is that not only are these objects, these Pareto curves, you know, efficient frontiers as you might call them, not only are they valuable scientific objects, I actually think that they in the near term might need to be the interface between researchers working in the field and stakeholders in given problems.

So, you know, you could really imagine telling a criminal jurisdiction, look, if you're concerned about racial fairness, but you're also concerned about accuracy, you want to, you know, you want to release on parole people that are not going to recommit a violent crime and you don't want to release the ones who are.

So, you know, that's accuracy. But if you also care about those, you know, the mistakes you make not being disproportionately on one racial group or another, you can show this curve. I'm hoping that in the near future, it'll be possible to explain these curves to non-technical people that are the ones that have to make the decision, where do we want to be on this curve?

Like, what are the relative merits or value of having lower error versus lower unfairness? You know, that's not something computer scientists should be deciding for society, right? That, you know, the people in the field, so to speak, the policy makers, the regulators, that's who should be making these decisions.

But I think and hope that they can be made to understand that these trade-offs generally exist and that you need to pick a point and like, and ignoring the trade-off, you know, you're implicitly picking a point anyway, right? You just don't know it and you're not admitting it. Just to linger on the point of trade-offs, I think that's a really important thing to sort of think about.

So you think when we start to optimize for fairness, there's almost always in most system going to be trade-offs. Can you, like, what's the trade-off between, just to clarify, there've been some sort of technical terms thrown around, but sort of a perfectly fair world, why is that, why will somebody be upset about that?

The specific trade-off I talked about just in order to make things very concrete was between numerical error and some numerical measure of unfairness. What is numerical error in the case of... Just like, say, predictive error, like, you know, the probability or frequency with which you release somebody on parole who then goes on to recommit a violent crime or keep incarcerated somebody who would not have recommitted a violent crime.

So in the case of awarding somebody parole or giving somebody parole or letting them out on parole, you don't want them to recommit a crime. So it's your system failed in prediction if they happen to do a crime. Okay, so that's the performance, that's one axis. Right. And what's the fairness axis?

So then the fairness axis might be the difference between racial groups in the kind of false, false positive predictions, namely people that I kept incarcerated predicting that they would recommit a violent crime when in fact they wouldn't have. Right. And the unfairness of that, just to linger it and allow me to ineloquently to try to sort of describe why that's unfair, why unfairness is there.

The unfairness you want to get rid of is that in the judge's mind, the bias of having being brought up to society, the slight racial bias, the racism that exists in the society, you want to remove that from the system. Another way that's been debated is sort of equality of opportunity versus equality of outcome.

And there's a weird dance there that's really difficult to get right. And we don't, it's what the affirmative action is exploring that space. Right. And then we, this also quickly bleeds into questions like, well, maybe if one group really does recommit crimes at a higher rate, the reason for that is that at some earlier point in the pipeline or earlier in their lives, they didn't receive the same resources that the other group did.

Right. And that, and so, there's always in kind of fairness discussions, the possibility that the real injustice came earlier, right? Earlier in this individual's life, earlier in this group's history, et cetera, et cetera. And so, a lot of the fairness discussion is almost, the goal is for it to be a corrective mechanism to account for the injustice earlier in life.

By some definitions of fairness or some theories of fairness, yeah. Others would say like, look, it's not to correct that injustice, it's just to kind of level the playing field right now and not incarcerate, falsely incarcerate more people of one group than another group. But I mean, do you think just, it might be helpful just to demystify a little bit about the many ways in which bias or unfairness can come into algorithms, especially in the machine learning era, right?

And I think many of your viewers have probably heard these examples before, but let's say I'm building a face recognition system, right? And so, I'm kind of gathering lots of images of faces and trying to train the system to recognize new faces of those individuals from training on a training set of those faces of individuals.

And it shouldn't surprise anybody, or certainly not anybody in the field of machine learning, if my training dataset was primarily white males, and I'm training the model to maximize the overall accuracy on my training dataset, that the model can reduce its error most by getting things right on the white males that constitute the majority of the dataset, even if that means that on other groups, they will be less accurate, okay?

Now, there's a bunch of ways you could think about addressing this. One is to deliberately put into the objective of the algorithm not to optimize the error at the expense of this discrimination, and then you're kind of back in the land of these kind of two-dimensional numerical trade-offs. A valid counter argument is to say like, "Well, no, you don't have to...

There's no... The notion of the tension between error and accuracy here is a false one." You could instead just go out and get much more data on these other groups that are in the minority and equalize your dataset, or you could train a separate model on those subgroups and have multiple models.

The point I think we would... We tried to make in the book is that those things have cost too, right? Going out and gathering more data on groups that are relatively rare compared to your plurality or majority group, that it may not cost you in the accuracy of the model, but it's going to cost the company developing this model more money to develop that, and it also costs more money to build separate predictive models and to implement and deploy them.

So even if you can find a way to avoid the tension between error and accuracy in training a model, you might push the cost somewhere else, like money, like development time, research time, and the like. There are fundamentally difficult philosophical questions, in fairness. And we live in a very divisive political climate, outrage culture.

There is alt-right folks on 4chan, trolls. There is social justice warriors on Twitter. There is very divisive, outraged folks on all sides of every kind of system. How do you, how do we as engineers build ethical algorithms in such divisive culture? Do you think they could be disjoint? The human has to inject your values, and then you can optimize over those values.

But in our times, when you start actually applying these systems, things get a little bit challenging for the public discourse. How do you think we can proceed? Yeah, I mean, for the most part, in the book, a point that we try to take some pains to make is that we don't view ourselves or people like us as being in the position of deciding for society what the right social norms are, what the right definitions of fairness are.

Our main point is to just show that if society or the relevant stakeholders in a particular domain can come to agreement on those sorts of things, there's a way of encoding that into algorithms in many cases, not in all cases. One other misconception that hopefully we definitely dispel is sometimes people read the title of the book and I think not unnaturally fear that what we're suggesting is that the algorithms themselves should decide what those social norms are and develop their own notions of fairness and privacy or ethics.

And we're definitely not suggesting that. The title of the book is Ethical Algorithm, by the way, and I didn't think of that interpretation of the title. That's interesting. Yeah, yeah. I mean, especially these days where people are concerned about the robots becoming our overlords, the idea that the robots would also sort of develop their own social norms is just one step away from that.

But I do think, obviously, despite disclaimer that people like us shouldn't be making those decisions for society, we are kind of living in a world where, in many ways, computer scientists have made some decisions that have fundamentally changed the nature of our society and democracy and sort of civil discourse and deliberation in ways that I think most people generally feel are bad these days, right?

So- But they had to make, so if we look at people at the heads of companies and so on, they had to make those decisions, right? There has to be decisions. So there's two options. Either you kind of put your head in the sand and don't think about these things and just let the algorithm do what it does, or you make decisions about what you value, you know, of injecting moral values into the algorithm.

Look, I never mean to be an apologist for the tech industry, but I think it's a little bit too far to sort of say that explicit decisions were made about these things. So let's, for instance, take social media platforms, right? So like many inventions in technology and computer science, a lot of these platforms that we now use regularly kind of started as curiosities, right?

I remember when things like Facebook came out and its predecessors like Friendster, which nobody even remembers now. People really wonder, like, why would anybody want to spend time doing that? I mean, even the web when it first came out, when it wasn't populated with much content and it was largely kind of hobbyists building their own kind of ramshackle websites, a lot of people looked at this as like, "Well, what is the purpose of this thing?

Why is this interesting? Who would want to do this?" And so even things like Facebook and Twitter, yes, technical decisions were made by engineers, by scientists, by executives in the design of those platforms. But I don't think 10 years ago anyone anticipated that those platforms, for instance, might kind of acquire undue influence on political discourse or on the outcomes of elections.

And I think the scrutiny that these companies are getting now is entirely appropriate, but I think it's a little too harsh to kind of look at history and sort of say like, "Oh, you should have been able to anticipate that this would happen with your platform." And in this sort of gaming chapter of the book, one of the points we're making is that these platforms, right, they don't operate in isolation.

So unlike the other topics we're discussing like fairness and privacy, those are really cases where algorithms can operate on your data and make decisions about you and you're not even aware of it, okay? Things like Facebook and Twitter, these are systems, right? These are social systems. And their evolution, even their technical evolution because machine learning is involved, is driven in no small part by the behavior of the users themselves and how the users decide to adopt them and how to use them.

And so I'm kind of like, "Who really knew that until we saw it happen? Who knew that these things might be able to influence the outcome of elections? Who knew that they might polarize political discourse because of the ability to decide who you interact with on the platform and also with the platform naturally using machine learning to optimize for your own interests that they would further isolate us from each other and feed us all basically just the stuff that we already agreed with?" And so I think we've come to that outcome, I think, largely, but I think it's something that we all learned together, including the companies, as these things happen.

Now, you asked like, "Well, are there algorithmic remedies to these kinds of things?" And again, these are big problems that are not going to be solved with somebody going in and changing a few lines of code somewhere in a social media platform. But I do think in many ways, there are definitely ways of making things better.

I mean, like an obvious recommendation that we make at some point in the book is like, "Look, to the extent that we think that machine learning applied for personalization purposes in things like news feed or other platforms has led to polarization and intolerance of opposing viewpoints," as you know, these algorithms have models, and they place people in some kind of metric space, and they place content in that space, and they know the extent to which I have an affinity for a particular type of content.

And by the same token, they also probably have... That same model probably gives you a good idea of the stuff I'm likely to violently disagree with or be offended by. So in this case, there really is some knob you could tune that says like, "Instead of showing people only what they like and what they want, let's show them some stuff that we think that they don't like or that's a little bit further away." And you could even imagine users being able to control this.

Just like everybody gets a slider, and that slider says like, "How much stuff do you want to see that's kind of you might disagree with or is at least further from your interests?" It's almost like an exploration button. - So just get your intuition. Do you think engagement... So like you're staying on the platform, you're staying engaged.

Do you think fairness, ideas of fairness won't emerge? Like how bad is it to just optimize for engagement? Do you think we'll run into big trouble if we're just optimizing for how much you love the platform? - Well, I mean, optimizing for engagement kind of got us where we are.

- So do you, one, have faith that it's possible to do better? And two, if it is, how do we do better? - I mean, it's definitely possible to do different, right? And again, it's not as if I think that doing something different than optimizing for engagement won't cost these companies in real ways, including revenue and profitability, potentially.

- In the short term, at least. - Yeah, in the short term, right. And again, if I worked at these companies, I'm sure that it would have seemed like the most natural thing in the world also to want to optimize engagement, right? And that's good for users in some sense.

You want them to be vested in the platform and enjoying it and finding it useful, interesting, and/or productive. But my point is is that the idea that it's sort of out of their hands, as you said, or that there's nothing to do about it, never say never, but that strikes me as implausible as a machine learning person, right?

I mean, these companies are driven by machine learning, and this optimization of engagement is essentially driven by machine learning, right? It's driven by not just machine learning, but very, very large-scale A/B experimentation where you kind of tweak some element of the user interface or tweak some component of an algorithm or tweak some component or feature of your click-through prediction model.

And my point is is that anytime you know how to optimize for something, almost by definition, that solution tells you how not to optimize for it or to do something different. - Engagement can be measured. So sort of optimizing for sort of minimizing divisiveness or maximizing intellectual growth over the lifetime of a human being are very difficult to measure.

- That's right. So I'm not claiming that doing something different will immediately make it apparent that this is a good thing for society. And in particular, I mean, I think one way of thinking about where we are on some of these social media platforms is it kind of feels a bit like we're in a bad equilibrium, right?

That these systems are helping us all kind of optimize something myopically and selfishly for ourselves. And of course, from an individual standpoint, at any given moment, like why would I want to see things in my newsfeed that I found irrelevant, offensive, or the like, okay? But maybe by all of us having these platforms myopically optimized in our interests, we have reached a collective outcome as a society that we're unhappy with in different ways, let's say with respect to things like political discourse and tolerance of opposing viewpoints.

- And if Mark Zuckerberg gave you a call and said, "I'm thinking of taking a sabbatical, could you run Facebook for me for six months?" What would you, how? - I think no thanks would be my first response, but there are many aspects of being the head of the entire company that are kind of entirely exogenous to many of the things that we're discussing here.

And so I don't really think I would need to be CEO of Facebook to kind of implement the more limited set of solutions that I might imagine. But I think one concrete thing they could do is they could experiment with letting people who chose to, to see more stuff in their newsfeed that is not entirely kind of chosen to optimize for their particular interests, beliefs, et cetera.

- So the kind of thing, I could speak to YouTube, but I think Facebook probably does something similar, is they're quite effective at automatically finding what sorts of groups you belong to, not based on race or gender or so on, but based on the kind of stuff you enjoy watching in the case of YouTube.

It's a difficult thing for Facebook or YouTube to then say, "Well, you know what? We're gonna show you something from a very different cluster, even though we believe algorithmically you're unlikely to enjoy that thing." So if that's a weird jump to make, there has to be a human at the very top of that system that says, "Well, that will be long-term healthy for you." That's more than an algorithmic decision.

- Or that same person could say, "That'll be long-term healthy for the platform." - For the platform. - Or for the platform's influence on society outside of the platform. And it's easy for me to sit here and say these things, but conceptually, I do not think that these are totally or they shouldn't be completely alien ideas.

You could try things like this, and we wouldn't have to invent entirely new science to do it, because if we're all already embedded in some metric space and there's a notion of distance between you and me and every piece of content, then we know exactly... The same model that dictates how to make me really happy also tells how to make me as unhappy as possible as well.

- Right. The focus in your book and algorithmic fairness research today in general is on machine learning, like we said, is data. And just even the entire AI field right now is captivated with machine learning, with deep learning. Do you think ideas in symbolic AI or totally other kinds of approaches are interesting, useful in the space, have some promising ideas in terms of fairness?

- I haven't thought about that question specifically in the context of fairness. I definitely would agree with that statement in the large, right? I mean, I am one of many machine learning researchers who do believe that the great successes that have been shown in machine learning recently are great successes, but they're on a pretty narrow set of tasks.

I mean, I don't think we're kind of notably closer to general artificial intelligence now than we were when I started my career. I mean, there's been progress. And I do think that we are kind of as a community maybe looking a bit where the light is, but the light is shining pretty bright there right now, and we're finding a lot of stuff.

So I don't want to like argue with the progress that's been made in areas like deep learning, for example. - This touches another sort of related thing that you mentioned, and that people might misinterpret from the title of your book, ethical algorithm. Is it possible for the algorithm to automate some of those decisions, sort of higher level decisions of what kind of...

- Like what should be fair. - What should be fair. - The more you know about a field, the more aware you are of its limitations. And so I'm pretty leery of sort of trying... There's so much we already don't know in fairness, even when we're the ones picking the fairness definitions and comparing alternatives and thinking about the tensions between different definitions, that the idea of kind of letting the algorithm start exploring as well, I definitely think, this is a much narrower statement.

I definitely think that kind of algorithmic auditing for different types of unfairness, right? So like in this gerrymandering example, where I might want to prevent not just discrimination against very broad categories, but against combinations of broad categories, you quickly get to a point where there's a lot of categories, there's a lot of combinations of end features.

And you can use algorithmic techniques to sort of try to find the subgroups on which you're discriminating the most and try to fix that. That's actually kind of the form of one of the algorithms we developed for this fairness gerrymandering problem. But I'm, you know, partly because of our technology and our sort of our scientific ignorance on these topics right now.

And also partly just because these topics are so loaded emotionally for people that I just don't see the value. I mean, again, never say never, but I just don't think we're at a moment where it's a great time for computer scientists to be rolling out the idea like, "Hey, you know, not only have we kind of figured fairness out, but, you know, we think the algorithms should start deciding what's fair or giving input on that decision." I just don't, it's like the cost benefit analysis to the field of kind of going there right now just doesn't seem worth it to me.

That said, I should say that I think computer scientists should be more philosophically, like should enrich their thinking about these kinds of things. I think it's been too often used as an excuse for roboticists working on autonomous vehicles, for example, to not think about the human factor or psychology or safety.

In the same way, like computer science design algorithms, they've been sort of using it as an excuse. And I think it's time for basically everybody to become computer scientists. I was about to agree with everything you said except that last point. I think that the other way of looking at it is that I think computer scientists, you know, and many of us are, but we need to wait out into the world more, right?

I mean, just the influence that computer science and therefore computer scientists have had on society at large just like has exponentially magnified in the last 10 or 20 years or so. And, you know, before when we were just tinkering around amongst ourselves and it didn't matter that much, there was no need for sort of computer scientists to be citizens of the world more broadly.

And I think those days need to be over very, very fast. And I'm not saying everybody needs to do it, but to me, like the right way of doing it is to not to sort of think that everybody else is going to become a computer scientist. But, you know, I think, you know, people are becoming more sophisticated about computer science, even lay people.

You know, I think one of the reasons we decided to write this book is we thought 10 years ago, I wouldn't have tried this just because I just didn't think that sort of people's awareness of algorithms and machine learning, you know, the general population would have been high. And I mean, you would have had to first, you know, write one of the many books kind of just explicating that topic to a lay audience first.

Now, I think we're at the point where like lots of people without any technical training at all know enough about algorithms and machine learning that you can start getting to these nuances of things like ethical algorithms. I think we agree that there needs to be much more mixing. But I think a lot of the onus of that mixing needs to be on the computer science community.

Yeah. So just to linger on the disagreement, because I do disagree with you on the point that I think if you're a biologist, if you're a chemist, if you're an MBA business person, all of those things you can, like, if you learned a program, and not only program, if you learn to do machine learning, if you learn to do data science, you immediately become much more powerful in the kinds of things you can do.

And therefore, literature, like library sciences, like, so you were speaking, I think, I think it holds true what you're saying for the next few years. But long term, if you're interested to me, if you're interested in philosophy, you should learn a program, because then you can scrape data, you can study what people are thinking about on Twitter, and then start making philosophical conclusions about the meaning of life.

Right? I just, I just feel like the access to data, the digitization of whatever problem you're trying to solve, it fundamentally changes what it means to be a computer scientist. I mean, computer scientists in 20, 30 years will go back to being Donald Knuth style theoretical computer science, and everybody would be doing, basically, they're exploring the kinds of ideas that you're exploring in your book.

It won't be a computer science major. Yeah, I mean, I don't think I disagree, but I think that that trend of more and more people in more and more disciplines, adopting ideas from computer science, learning how to code, I think that that trend seems firmly underway. I mean, you know, like, an interesting digressive question along these lines is maybe in 50 years, there won't be computer science departments anymore.

Because the field will just sort of be ambient in all of the different disciplines. And you know, people will look back and, you know, having a computer science department will look like having an electricity department or something. It's like, you know, everybody uses this, it's just out there. I mean, I do think there will always be that kind of Knuth style core to it.

But it's not an implausible path that we kind of get to the point where the academic discipline of computer science becomes somewhat marginalized, because of its very success in kind of infiltrating all of science and society and the humanities, etc. What is differential privacy, or more broadly, algorithmic privacy?

Algorithmic privacy more broadly is just the study or the notion of privacy definitions or norms being encoded inside of algorithms. And so, you know, I think we count among this body of work, just, you know, the literature and practice of things like data anonymization, which we kind of at the beginning of our discussion of privacy, say like, okay, this is sort of a notion of algorithmic privacy, it kind of tells you, you know, something to go do with data.

But, you know, our view is that it's, and I think this is now, you know, quite widespread, that it's, you know, despite the fact that those notions of anonymization, kind of redacting and coarsening, are the most widely adopted technical solutions for data privacy, they are like deeply, fundamentally flawed.

And so, you know, to your first question, what is differential privacy? Differential privacy seems to be a much, much better notion of privacy that kind of avoids a lot of the weaknesses of anonymization notions while still letting us do useful stuff with data. What's anonymization of data? So, by anonymization, I'm, you know, kind of referring to techniques like I have a database, the rows of that database are, let's say, individual people's medical records, okay?

And I want to let people use that data, maybe I want to let researchers access that data to build predictive models for some disease, but I'm worried that that will leak, you know, sensitive information about specific people's medical records. So, anonymization broadly refers to the set of techniques where I say, like, okay, I'm first going to, like, I'm going to delete the column with people's names.

I'm going to not put, you know, so that would be like a redaction, right? I'm just redacting that information. I am going to take ages, and I'm not going to, like, say your exact age, I'm going to say whether you're, you know, zero to 10, 10 to 20, 20 to 30.

I might put the first three digits of your zip code but not the last two, et cetera, et cetera. And so, the idea is that through some series of operations like this on the data, I anonymize it, you know, another term of art that's used is removing personally identifiable information.

And, you know, this is basically the most common way of providing data privacy but that's in a way that still lets people access some variant form of the data. >> So, at a slightly broader picture, as you talk about what does anonymization mean when you have multiple databases, like with a Netflix prize when you can start combining stuff together.

>> So, this is exactly the problem with these notions, right, is that notions of anonymization, removing personally identifiable information, the kind of fundamental conceptual flaw is that, you know, these definitions kind of pretend as if the data set in question is the only data set that exists in the world or that ever will exist in the future.

And, of course, things like the Netflix prize and many, many other examples since the Netflix prize, I think that was one of the earliest ones, though, you know, you can reidentify people that were, you know, that were anonymized in the data set by taking that anonymized data set and combining it with other allegedly anonymized data sets and maybe publicly available information about you.

>> And for people who don't know, the Netflix prize was being publicly released as data. So, the names from those rows were removed but what was released is the preference or the ratings of what movies you like and you don't like. And from that combined with other things, I think forum posts and so on, you can start to figure out the names.

>> Yeah, I mean, in that case, it was specifically the internet movie database. >> The ad data. >> Where lots of Netflix users publicly rate their movie, you know, their movie preferences. And so, the anonymized data in Netflix when kind of, you know, it's just this phenomenon, I think, we've all come to realize in the last decade or so is that just knowing a few apparently irrelevant innocuous things about you can often act as a fingerprint.

Like if I know, you know, what rating you gave to these 10 movies and the date on which you entered these movies, this is almost like a fingerprint for you in the sea of all Netflix users. There was just another paper on this in Science or Nature about a month ago that, you know, kind of 18 attributes.

I mean, my favorite example of this was actually a paper from several years ago now where it was shown that just from your likes on Facebook, just from the, you know, the things on which you clicked on the thumbs up button on the platform, not using any information, demographic information, nothing about who your friends are, just knowing the content that you had liked was enough to, you know, in the aggregate accurately predict things like sexual orientation, drug and alcohol use, whether you were the child of divorced parents.

So we live in this era where, you know, even the apparently irrelevant data that we offer about ourselves on public platforms and forums often unbeknownst to us more or less acts as a signature or, you know, fingerprint. And that if you can kind of, you know, do a join between that kind of data and allegedly anonymized data, you have real trouble.

So is there hope for any kind of privacy in a world where a few likes can identify you? So there is differential privacy, right? So what is differential privacy? So differential privacy basically is a kind of alternate, much stronger notion of privacy than these anonymization ideas. And it, you know, it's a technical definition, but like the spirit of it is we compare two alternate worlds, okay?

So let's suppose I'm a researcher and I want to do, you know, there's a database of medical records and one of them is yours. And I want to use that database of medical records to build a predictive model for some disease. So based on people's symptoms and test results and the like, I want to, you know, build a model predicting the probability that people have disease.

So, you know, this is the type of scientific research that we would like to be allowed to continue. And in differential privacy, you ask a very particular counterfactual question. We basically compare two alternatives. One is when I do this, I build this model on the database of medical records, including your medical record.

And the other one is where I do the same exercise with the same database with just your medical record removed. So basically, you know, it's two databases, one with N records in it and one with N minus one records in it. The N minus one records are the same and the only one that's missing in the second case is your medical record.

So differential privacy basically says that any harms that might come to you from the analysis in which your data was included are essentially nearly identical to the harms that would have come to you if the same analysis had done been done without your medical record included. So in other words, this doesn't say that bad things cannot happen to you as a result of data analysis.

It just says that these bad things were going to happen to you already, even if your data wasn't included. And to give a very concrete example, right, you know, like we discussed at some length, the study that, you know, in the '50s that was done that created the, that established the link between smoking and lung cancer.

And we make the point that like, well, if your data was used in that analysis and, you know, the world kind of knew that you were a smoker because, you know, there was no stigma associated with smoking before that, those findings, real harm might've come to you as a result of that study that your data was included in.

In particular, your insurer now might have a higher posterior belief that you might have lung cancer and raise your premium. So you've suffered economic damage. But the point is, is that if the same analysis has been done without, with all the other N minus one medical records and just yours missing, the outcome would have been the same.

Your data wasn't idiosyncratically crucial to establishing the link between smoking and lung cancer, because the link between smoking and lung cancer is like a fact about the world that can be discovered with any sufficiently large database of medical records. >> But that's a very low value of harm. Yeah, so that's showing that very little harm is done.

Great. But how, what is the mechanism of differential privacy? So that's the kind of beautiful statement of it. But what's the mechanism by which privacy is preserved? >> Yeah. So it's basically by adding noise to computations, right? So the basic idea is that every differentially private algorithm, first of all, or every good differentially private algorithm, every useful one is a probabilistic algorithm.

So it doesn't, on a given input, if you gave the algorithm the same input multiple times, it would give different outputs each time from some distribution. And the way you achieve differential privacy algorithmically is by kind of carefully and tastefully adding noise to a computation in the right places.

And to give a very concrete example, if I want to compute the average of a set of numbers, right, the non-private way of doing that is to take those numbers and average them and release a numerically precise value for the average, okay? In differential privacy, you wouldn't do that.

You would first compute that average to numerical precisions, and then you'd add some noise to it, right? You'd add some kind of zero mean, Gaussian or exponential noise to it, so that the actual value you output is not the exact mean, but it'll be close to the mean, but it'll be close, the noise that you add will sort of prove that nobody can kind of reverse engineer any particular value that went into the average.

>> So noise is the savior. How many algorithms can be aided by adding noise? >> Yeah, so I'm a relatively recent member of the differential privacy community. My co-author, Aaron Roth, is, you know, really one of the founders of the field and has done a great deal of work, and I've learned a tremendous amount working with him on it.

>> It's a pretty grown-up field already. >> Yeah, but now it's pretty mature. But I must admit, the first time I saw the definition of differential privacy, my reaction was like, "Well, that is a clever definition, and it's really making very strong promises." And my, you know, I first saw the definition in much earlier days, and my first reaction was like, "Well, my worry about this definition would be that it's a great definition of privacy, but that it'll be so restrictive that we won't really be able to use it." Like, you know, we won't be able to compute many things in a differentially private way.

So that's one of the great successes of the field, I think, is in showing that the opposite is true, and that, you know, most things that we know how to compute, absent any privacy considerations, can be computed in a differentially private way. So, for example, pretty much all of statistics and machine learning can be done differentially privately.

So pick your favorite machine learning algorithm, back propagation and neural networks, you know, cart for decision trees, support vector machines, boosting, you name it, as well as classic hypothesis testing and the like in statistics. None of those algorithms are differentially private in their original form. All of them have modifications that add noise to the computation in different places in different ways that achieve differential privacy.

So this really means that to the extent that, you know, we've become a, you know, a scientific community very dependent on the use of machine learning and statistical modeling and data analysis, we really do have a path to kind of provide privacy guarantees to those methods. And so we can still, you know, enjoy the benefits of kind of the data science era while providing, you know, rather robust privacy guarantees to individuals.

So perhaps a slightly crazy question, but if we take the ideas of differential privacy and take it to the nature of truth that's being explored currently, so what's your most favorite and least favorite food? Hmm, I'm not a real foodie, so I'm a big fan of spaghetti. Spaghetti? Yeah.

And what do you really don't like? Um, I really don't like cauliflower. Wow, I love cauliflower. Okay. But is one way to protect your preference for spaghetti by having an information campaign, bloggers and so on, of bots saying that you like cauliflower. So like this kind of, the same kind of noise ideas.

I mean, if you think of in our politics today, there's this idea of Russia hacking our elections. What's meant there, I believe, is bots spreading different kinds of information. Is that a kind of privacy or is that too much of a stretch? No, it's not a stretch. I've not seen those ideas, you know, that is not a technique that to my knowledge will provide differential privacy.

But to give an example, like one very specific example about what you're discussing is, there was a very interesting project at NYU, I think led by Helen Nissenbaum there, in which they basically built a browser plugin that tried to essentially obfuscate your Google searches. So to the extent that you're worried that Google is using your searches to build, you know, predictive models about you, to decide what ads to show you, which they might very reasonably want to do.

But if you object to that, they built this widget you could plug in. And basically, whenever you put in a query into Google, it would send that query to Google. But in the background, all of the time from your browser, it would just be sending this torrent of irrelevant queries to the search engine.

So, you know, it's like a weed and chaff thing. So, you know, out of every thousand queries, let's say, that Google was receiving from your browser, one of them was one that you put in, but the other 999 were not. Okay, so it's the same kind of idea, kind of, you know, privacy by obfuscation.

So I think that's an interesting idea. Doesn't give you differential privacy. It's also, I was actually talking to somebody at one of the large tech companies recently about the fact that, you know, just this kind of thing that there are some times when the response to my data needs to be very specific to my data, right?

Like, I type mountain biking into Google, I want results on mountain biking, and I really want Google to know that I typed in mountain biking. I don't want noise added to that. And so I think there's sort of maybe even interesting technical questions around notions of privacy that are appropriate where, you know, it's not that my data is part of some aggregate like medical records and that we're trying to discover important correlations and facts about the world at large, but rather, you know, there's a service that I really want to, you know, pay attention to my specific data, yet I still want some kind of privacy guarantee.

And I think these kind of obfuscation ideas are sort of one way of getting at that, but maybe there are others as well. So where do you think we'll land in this algorithm driven society in terms of privacy? So, sort of, China, like Kai-Fu Lee describes, you know, it's collecting a lot of data on its citizens, but in the best form, it's actually able to provide a lot of, sort of, protect human rights and provide a lot of amazing services.

And it's worse forms that can violate those human rights and limit services. So where do you think we'll land? So algorithms are powerful when they use data. So as a society, do you think we'll give over more data? Is it possible to protect the privacy of that data? So I'm optimistic about the possibility of, you know, balancing the desire for individual privacy and individual control of privacy with kind of societally and commercially beneficial uses of data, not unrelated to differential privacy or suggestions that say like, well, individuals should have control of their data.

They should be able to limit the uses of that data. They should even, you know, there's, you know, fledgling discussions going on in research circles about allowing people selective use of their data and being compensated for it. And then you get to sort of very interesting economic questions like pricing, right?

And one interesting idea is that maybe differential privacy would also, you know, be a conceptual framework in which you could talk about the relative value of different people's data, like, you know, to demystify this a little bit. If I'm trying to build a predictive model for some rare disease and I'm going to use machine learning to do it, it's easy to get negative examples because the disease is rare, right?

But I really want to have lots of people with the disease in my data set, okay? And so somehow those people's data with respect to this application is much more valuable to me than just like the background population. And so maybe they should be compensated more for it. And so, you know, I think these are kind of very, very fledgling conceptual questions that maybe we'll have kind of technical thought on them sometime in the coming years.

But I do think we'll, you know, to kind of get more directly answer your question, I think I'm optimistic at this point from what I've seen that we will land at some, you know, better compromise than we're at right now, where again, you know, privacy guarantees are few, far between, and weak, and users have very, very little control.

And I'm optimistic that we'll land in something that, you know, provides better privacy overall and more individual control of data and privacy. But, you know, I think to get there, it's again, just like fairness, it's not going to be enough to propose algorithmic solutions. There's going to have to be a whole kind of regulatory legal process that prods companies and other parties to kind of adopt solutions.

>> And I think you've mentioned the word control a lot. And I think giving people control, that's something that people don't quite have in a lot of these algorithms. And that's a really interesting idea of giving them control. Some of that is actually literally an interface design question, sort of just enabling, because I think it's good for everybody to give users control.

It's not, it's not a, it's almost not a trade-off, except that you have to hire people that are good at interface design. >> Yeah, I mean, the other thing that has to be said, right, is that, you know, it's a cliche, but, you know, we, as the users of many systems, platforms, and apps, you know, we are the product.

We are not the customer. The customer are advertisers, and our data is the product, okay? So it's one thing to kind of suggest more individual control of data and privacy and uses, but this, you know, if this happens in sufficient degree, it will upend the entire economic model that has supported the internet to date.

And so some other economic model will have to be, you know, will have to replace it. >> So the idea of markets you mentioned, by exposing the economic model to the people, they will then become a market, and therefore— >> They could be participants in it. >> Participants in it.

>> And, you know, this isn't, you know, this is not a weird idea, right? Because there are markets for data already. It's just that consumers are not participants in that. There's like, you know, there's sort of, you know, publishers and content providers on one side that have inventory, and then they're advertising on the others, and, you know, Google and Facebook are running, you know, their—pretty much their entire revenue stream is by running two-sided markets between those parties, right?

And so it's not a crazy idea that there would be like a three-sided market or that, you know, that on one side of the market or the other, we would have proxies representing our interest. It's not, you know, it's not a crazy idea, but it would—it's not a crazy technical idea, but it would have pretty extreme economic consequences.

>> Speaking of markets, a lot of fascinating aspects of this world arise not from individual humans, but from the interaction of human beings. You've done a lot of work in game theory. First, can you say what is game theory and how does it help us model and study things?

>> Yeah, game theory, of course, let us give credit where it's due. You know, it comes from the economists first and foremost, but as I've mentioned before, like, you know, computer scientists never hesitate to wander into other people's turf, and so there is now this 20-year-old field called algorithmic game theory.

But, you know, game theory, first and foremost, is a mathematical framework for reasoning about collective outcomes in systems of interacting individuals. You know, so you need at least two people to get started in game theory, and many people are probably familiar with Prisoner's Dilemma as kind of a classic example of game theory and a classic example where everybody looking out for their own individual interests leads to a collective outcome that's kind of worse for everybody than what might be possible if they cooperated, for example.

But cooperation is not an equilibrium in Prisoner's Dilemma. And so my work and the field of algorithmic game theory more generally in these areas kind of looks at settings in which the number of actors is potentially extraordinarily large and their incentives might be quite complicated and kind of hard to model directly, but you still want kind of algorithmic ways of kind of predicting what will happen or influencing what will happen in the design of platforms.

>> So what to you is the most beautiful idea that you've encountered in game theory? >> There's a lot of them. I'm a big fan of the field. I mean, you know, I mean, technical answers to that, of course, would include Nash's work just establishing that, you know, there's a competitive equilibrium under very, very general circumstances, which in many ways kind of put the field on a firm conceptual footing, because if you don't have equilibrium, it's kind of hard to ever reason about what might happen since, you know, there's just no stability.

>> So just the idea that stability can emerge when there's multiple... >> Or that, I mean, not that it will necessarily emerge, just that it's possible, right? I mean, like the existence of equilibrium doesn't mean that sort of natural iterative behavior will necessarily lead to it. >> In the real world, yes.

>> Yeah. Maybe answering slightly less personally than you asked the question, I think within the field of algorithmic game theory, perhaps the single most important kind of technical contribution that's been made is the realization between close connections between machine learning and game theory, and in particular between game theory and the branch of machine learning that's known as no-regret learning.

And this sort of provides a very general framework in which a bunch of players interacting in a game or a system, each one kind of doing something that's in their self interest will actually kind of reach an equilibrium, and actually reach an equilibrium in a pretty, you know, a rather, you know, short amount of steps.

>> So you kind of mentioned acting greedily can somehow end up pretty good for everybody. >> Or pretty bad. >> Or pretty bad. It'll end up stable. >> Yeah, right. And, you know, stability or equilibrium by itself is not necessarily either a good thing or a bad thing. >> So what's the connection between machine learning and the ideas of equilibrium?

>> Well, I mean, I think we've kind of talked about these ideas already in kind of a non-technical way, which is maybe the more interesting way of understanding them first, which is, you know, we have many systems, platforms, and apps these days that work really hard to use our data and the data of everybody else on the platform to selfishly optimize on behalf of each user, okay?

So, you know, let me give, I think, the cleanest example, which is just driving apps, navigation apps like, you know, Google Maps and Waze, where, you know, miraculously compared to when I was growing up at least, you know, the objective would be the same when you wanted to drive from point A to point B, spend the least time driving, not necessarily minimize the distance, but minimize the time, right?

And when I was growing up, like, the only resources you had to do that were, like, maps in the car, which literally just told you what roads were available. And then you might have, like, half-hourly traffic reports just about the major freeways, but not about side roads. So you were pretty much on your own.

And now we've got these apps, you pull it out and you say, "I want to go from point A to point B." And in response kind of to what everybody else is doing, if you like, what all the other players in this game are doing right now, here's the, you know, the route that minimizes your driving time.

So it is really kind of computing a selfish best response for each of us in response to what all of the rest of us are doing at any given moment. And so, you know, I think it's quite fair to think of these apps as driving or nudging us all towards the competitive or Nash equilibrium of that game.

Now you might ask, like, "Well, that sounds great. Why is that a bad thing?" Well, you know, it's known both in theory and with some limited studies from actual, like, traffic data that all of us being in this competitive equilibrium might cause our collective driving time to be higher, maybe significantly higher than it would be under other solutions.

And then you have to talk about what those other solutions might be and what the algorithms to implement them are, which we do discuss in the kind of game theory chapter of the book. But similarly, you know, on social media platforms or on Amazon, you know, all these algorithms that are essentially trying to optimize our behalf, they're driving us in a colloquial sense towards some kind of competitive equilibrium.

And, you know, one of the most important lessons of game theory is that just because we're at equilibrium doesn't mean that there's not a solution in which some or maybe even all of us might be better off. And then the connection to machine learning, of course, is that in all these platforms I've mentioned, the optimization that they're doing on our behalf is driven by machine learning, you know, like predicting where the traffic will be, predicting what products I'm going to like, predicting what would make me happy in my news feed.

Now, in terms of the stability and the promise of that, I have to ask, just out of curiosity, how stable are these mechanisms that you, game theory is just, the economists came up with, and we all know that economists don't live in the real world, just kidding. Sort of what's, do you think when we look at the fact that we haven't blown ourselves up from a game theoretic concept of mutually shared destruction, what are the odds that we destroy ourselves with nuclear weapons as one example of a stable game theoretic system?

>>Just to prime your viewers a little bit, I mean, I think you're referring to the fact that game theory was taken quite seriously back in the '60s as a tool for reasoning about kind of Soviet US nuclear armament, disarmament, detente, things like that. I'll be honest, as huge of a fan as I am of game theory and its kind of rich history, it still surprises me that you had people at the Rand Corporation back in those days kind of drawing up two by two tables and one, the row player is the US and the column player is Russia, and that they were taking seriously, I'm sure if I was there, maybe it wouldn't have seemed as naive as it does at the time.

>>It seems to have worked, which is why it seems naive and silly. >>Well, we're still here. >>We're still here in that sense. >>Yeah. Even though I kind of laugh at those efforts, they were more sensible then than they would be now, right? Because there were sort of only two nuclear powers at the time, and you didn't have to worry about deterring new entrants and who was developing the capacity.

And so we have many, we have this, it's definitely a game with more players now and more potential entrants. I'm not in general somebody who advocates using kind of simple mathematical models when the stakes are as high as things like that, and the complexities are very political and social, but we are still here.

>>So you've worn many hats, one of which, the one that first caused me to become a big fan of your work many years ago is algorithmic trading. So I have to just ask a question about this because you have so much fascinating work there. In the 21st century, what role do you think algorithms have in the space of trading, investment in the financial sector?

>>Yeah, it's a good question. I mean, in the time I've spent on Wall Street and in finance, I've seen a clear progression, and I think it's a progression that kind of models the use of algorithms and automation more generally in society, which is the things that kind of get taken over by the algos first are sort of the things that computers are obviously better at than people, right?

So first of all, there needed to be this era of automation, right, where just financial exchanges became largely electronic, which then enabled the possibility of trading becoming more algorithmic because once the exchanges are electronic, an algorithm can submit an order through an API just as well as a human can do at a monitor.

>>It can do it really quickly. It can read all the data. >>Yeah. And so I think the places where algorithmic trading have had the greatest inroads and had the first inroads were in kind of execution problems, kind of optimized execution problems. So what I mean by that is at a large brokerage firm, for example, one of the lines of business might be on behalf of large institutional clients taking what we might consider difficult trades.

So it's not like a mom and pop investor saying, "I want to buy 100 shares of Microsoft." It's a large hedge fund saying, "I want to buy a very, very large stake in Apple, and I want to do it over the span of a day." And it's such a large volume that if you're not clever about how you break that trade up, not just over time, but over perhaps multiple different electronic exchanges that all let you trade Apple on their platform, you'll push prices around in a way that hurts your execution.

So this is an optimization problem. This is a control problem. And so machines are better. We know how to design algorithms that are better at that kind of thing than a person is going to be able to do because we can take volumes of historical and real-time data to kind of optimize the schedule with which we trade.

And similarly, high-frequency trading, which is closely related but not the same as optimized execution, where you're just trying to spot very, very temporary mispricings between exchanges or within an asset itself, or just predict directional movement of a stock because of the kind of very, very low-level, granular buying and selling data in the exchange, machines are good at this kind of stuff.

It's kind of like the mechanics of trading. What about the... Can machines do long-term sort of prediction? Yeah. So I think we are in an era where clearly there have been some very successful quant hedge funds that are in what we would traditionally call still in the stat-arb regime.

So... What's that? Stat-arb referring to statistical arbitrage. But for the purposes of this conversation, what it really means is making directional predictions in asset price movement or returns. Your prediction about that directional movement is good for... You have a view that it's valid for some period of time between a few seconds and a few days.

And that's the amount of time that you're going to kind of get into the position, hold it, and then hopefully be right about the directional movement and buy low and sell high as the cliche goes. So that is kind of a sweet spot, I think, for quant trading and investing right now and has been for some time.

When you really get to kind of more Warren Buffett-style time scales, like my cartoon of Warren Buffett is that Warren Buffett sits and thinks what the long-term value of Apple really should be. And he doesn't even look at what Apple is doing today. He just decides, "I think that this is what its long-term value is, and it's far from that right now.

And so I'm going to buy some Apple or short some Apple, and I'm going to sit on that for 10 or 20 years." Okay. So when you're at that kind of time scale or even more than just a few days, you raise all kinds of other sources of risk and information.

So now you're talking about holding things through recessions and economic cycles. Wars can break out. So there you have to understand human nature at a level that— Yeah. And you need to just be able to ingest many, many more sources of data that are on wildly different time scales, right?

So if I'm an HFT, I'm a high-frequency trader, I really—my main source of data is just the data from the exchanges themselves about the activity in the exchanges, right? And maybe I need to pay—I need to keep an eye on the news, right? Because that can cause sudden—the CEO gets caught in a scandal or gets run over by a bus or something that can cause very sudden changes.

But I don't need to understand economic cycles. I don't need to understand recessions. I don't need to worry about the political situation or war breaking out in this part of the world because all I need to know is as long as that's not going to happen in the next 500 milliseconds, then my model is good.

When you get to these longer time scales, you really have to worry about that kind of stuff. And people in the machine learning community are starting to think about this. We held a—we jointly sponsored a workshop at Penn with the Federal Reserve Bank of Philadelphia a little more than a year ago on—I think the title was something like Machine Learning for Macroeconomic Prediction, macroeconomic referring specifically to these longer time scales.

And it was an interesting conference, but it left me with greater confidence that we have a long way to go to—and so I think that people that—in the grand scheme of things, so somebody asked me like, "Well, whose job on Wall Street is safe from the bots?" I think people that are at that longer time scale and have that appetite for all the risks involved in long-term investing and that really need kind of not just algorithms that can optimize from data, but they need views on stuff.

They need views on the political landscape, economic cycles and the like. And I think they're pretty safe for a while as far as I can tell. So Warren Buffett's job is safe for a little while. Yeah, I'm not seeing a robo-Warren Buffett anytime soon. Should give him comfort. Last question.

If you could go back to—if there's a day in your life you could relive because it made you truly happy, maybe in your outside family. Yeah, otherwise we'd be out here. What day would it be? Can you look back, you remember just being profoundly transformed in some way or blissful?

I'll answer a slightly different question, which is like, what's a day in my life or my career that was kind of a watershed moment? Yes. I went straight from undergrad to doctoral studies, and that's not at all atypical. And I'm also from an academic family. Like my dad was a professor, my uncle on his side is a professor, both my grandfathers were professors.

All kinds of majors too, philosophy, I saw. Yeah, they're kind of all over the map, yeah. And I was a grad student here just up the river at Harvard and came to study with Les Valiant, which was a wonderful experience. But I remember my first year of graduate school, I was generally pretty unhappy.

And I was unhappy because at Berkeley as an undergraduate, yeah, I studied a lot of math and computer science, but it was a huge school, first of all. And I took a lot of other courses, as we discussed, I started as an English major and took history courses and art history classes and had friends that did all kinds of different things.

And Harvard's a much smaller institution than Berkeley, and its computer science department, especially at that time, was a much smaller place than it is now. And I suddenly just felt very, like I'd gone from this very big world to this highly specialized world. And now all of the classes I was taking were computer science classes, and I was only in classes with math and computer science people.

And so I was, I thought often in that first year of grad school about whether I really wanted to stick with it or not. And I thought like, "Oh, I could stop with a master's, I could go back to the Bay Area and to California, and this was in one of the early periods where there was, you could definitely get a relatively good job, paying job at one of the tech companies back, that were the big tech companies back then." And so I distinctly remember like kind of a late spring day when I was kind of sitting in Boston Common and kind of really just kind of chewing over what I wanted to do in my life.

And then I realized like, "Okay," and I think this is where my academic background helped me a great deal. I sort of realized, "Yeah, you're not having a great time right now, this feels really narrowing, but you know that you're here for research eventually, and to do something original, and to try to carve out a career where you kind of choose what you want to think about and have a great deal of independence." And so at that point, I really didn't have any real research experience yet.

I mean, it was trying to think about some problems with very little success, but I knew that like I hadn't really tried to do the thing that I knew I'd come to do. And so I thought, you know, "I'm going to stick through it for the summer," and that was very formative because I went from kind of contemplating quitting to, you know, a year later, it being very clear to me I was going to finish because I still had a ways to go, but I kind of started doing research, it was going well, it was really interesting, and it was sort of a complete transformation.

You know, and it's just that transition that I think every doctoral student makes at some point, which is to sort of go from being like a student of what's been done before to doing, you know, your own thing and figure out what makes you interested and what your strengths and weaknesses are as a researcher.

And once, you know, I kind of made that decision on that particular day at that particular moment in Boston Common, you know, I'm glad I made that decision. And also just accepting the painful nature of that journey. Yeah, yeah, exactly, exactly. And in that moment said, "I'm gonna stick it out." Yeah, I'm gonna stick around for a while.

Well, Michael, I've looked up to your work for a long time, it's really an honor to talk to you. Thank you so much for doing it. It's great to get back in touch with you too and see how great you're doing as well. So thanks a lot, appreciate it.

Thanks, Michael. Thanks. you you you you you you you you you you you you you